Footnotes to Plato from the foothills of the Superstition Mountains

Is Trump’s Order to End DEI Conservative?

From the Independent Institute:

President Trump signed a flurry of executive orders last week, leaving media pundits breathless in their efforts to cover it all. One of the most controversial orders was titled “Ending Radical and Wasteful Government DEI Programs and Preferencing.”

Yes, conservatives applauded loudly the government’s suspension of its commitment to DEI (diversity, equity, and inclusion)—but the order wasn’t conservative. The history of colorblind meritocracy is a classical liberal one that originated from neither the Left nor Right.

I beg to differ.  Commitment to race-neutral meritocracy is indeed classically liberal,  but classical liberalism is an essential ingredient in American conservatism. This is more than a terminological quibble: it is a disagreement over the nature of American conservatism.

For many of us who reject leftism, and embrace a version of conservatism, there remains a choice between what I call American conservatism, which accepts key tenets of classical liberalism, and a more robust conservatism.  This more robust conservatism inclines toward the reactionary and anti-liberal. The difference emerges in an essay by Bishop Robert Barron entitled One Cheer for George Will's The Conservative Sensibility. The bolded passages below throw the difference into relief.

And so it was with great interest that I turned to Will’s latest offering, a massive volume called The Conservative Sensibility, a book that both in size and scope certainly qualifies as the author’s opus magnum. Will’s central argument is crucially important. The American experiment in democracy rests, he says, upon the epistemological [sic] conviction that there are political rights, grounded in a relatively stable human nature, that precede the actions and decisions of government. These rights to life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness are not the gifts of the state; rather, the state exists to guarantee them, or to use the word that Will considers the most important in the entire prologue to the Declaration of Independence, to “secure” them. Thus is government properly and severely limited and tyranny kept, at least in principle, at bay. In accord with both Hobbes and Locke, Will holds that the purpose of the government finally is to provide an arena for the fullest possible expression of individual freedom. [. . .]

With much of this I found myself in profound agreement. It is indeed a pivotal feature of Catholic social teaching that an objective human nature exists and that the rights associated with it are inherent and not artificial constructs of the culture or the state. Accordingly, it is certainly good that government’s tendency toward imperial expansion be constrained. But as George Will’s presentation unfolded, I found myself far less sympathetic with his vision. What becomes clear is that Will shares, with Hobbes and Locke and their disciple Thomas Jefferson, a morally minimalistic understanding of the arena of freedom that government exists to protect. All three of those modern political theorists denied that we can know with certitude the true nature of human happiness or the proper goal of the moral life—and hence they left the determination of those matters up to the individual. Jefferson expressed this famously as the right to pursue happiness as one sees fit. The government’s role, on this interpretation, is to assure the least conflict among the myriad individuals seeking their particular version of fulfillment. The only moral bedrock in this scenario is the life and freedom of each actor.

Catholic social teaching has long been suspicious of just this sort of morally minimalist individualism. Central to the Church’s thinking on politics is the conviction that ethical principles, available to the searching intellect of any person of good will, ought to govern the moves [sic] of individuals within the society, and moreover, that the nation as a whole ought to be informed by a clear sense of the common good—that is to say, some shared social value that goes beyond simply what individuals might seek for themselves. Pace Will, the government itself plays a role in the application of this moral framework precisely in the measure that law has both a protective and directive function. It both holds off threats to human flourishing and, since it is, to a degree, a teacher of what the society morally approves and disapproves, also actively guides the desires of citizens.

I applaud the idea that the law have both a protective and a directive function.  But to what should the law direct us? 

On a purely procedural liberalism, "the purpose of the government finally is to provide an arena for the fullest possible expression of individual freedom. " This won't do, obviously. If people are allowed the fullest possible expression of individual freedom, then anything goes: looting, arson, bestiality, paedophilia, voter fraud, lying under oath, destruction of public and private property, etc.  Liberty is a high value but not when it becomes license. Indisputably, ethical principles ought to govern the behavior of individuals. But which principles exactly? Therein lies the rub. We will presumably agree that there must be some, but this agreement gets us nowhere unless we can specify the principles.

If we knew "with certitude the true nature of human happiness or the proper goal of the moral life" then we could derive the principles. Now there are those who are subjectively certain about the nature of happiness and the goal of life.   But this merely subjective certainty is worth little or nothing given that different people and groups are 'certain' about different things.  Subjective certainty is no guarantee of objective certainty, which is what knowledge requires.  This is especially so if the putative knowledge will be used to justify ethical prescriptions and proscriptions that will be imposed upon people by law.

For example, there are atheists and there are theists in almost every society. No atheist could possibly believe that the purpose of human life is to know, love, and serve God in this world and be happy with him in the next.  From this Catechism answer one can derive very specific ethical prescriptions and proscriptions, some of which will be rejected by atheists as a violation of their liberty. Now if one could KNOW that the Catechism answer is true, then those specific ethical principles would be objectively grounded in a manner that would justify imposing them on all members of a society for their own good whether they like it or not.

But is it known, as opposed to reasonably believed, that there is a God, etc.?  Most atheists would deny that the proposition in question is even reasonably believed.  Bishop Barron's Catholicism is to their minds just so much medieval superstition. Suppose, however, that the good bishop's worldview is simply true.  That does us no good unless we can know that it is true. Suppose some know (with objective certainty) that it is true. That also does us no good, politically speaking, unless a large majority in a society can agree that we know that it is true. 

So while it cannot be denied that the law must have some directive, as opposed to merely protective, function, the question remains as to what precisely it ought to direct us to.  The directions cannot come from any religion, but neither can they come from any ersatz religion such as leftism.  No theocracy, but also no 'leftocracy'!  Separation of church and state, but also separation of leftism and state.

This leaves us with the problem of finding the via media between a purely procedural liberalism and the tyrannical imposition of  prescriptions and proscriptions that derive from some dogmatically held, but strictly unknowable, set of metaphysical assumptions about man and world.  It is a dilemma inasmuch as both options are unacceptable.  

I'll end by noting that the main threats to our liberty at the present time do not emanate from a Roman Catholicism that has become a shell of its former self bereft of the cultural relevance it enjoyed for millennia until losing it in the mid-1960s; they proceed from leftism and Islam, and the Unholy Alliance of the two.

And so while the dilemma lately noted remains in force, a partial solution must take the form of retaining elements of the Judeo-Christian worldview, the Ten Commandments chiefly,  and by a restoration of the values of the American founding. Practically, this will require vigorous opposition to the parties of the unholy alliance.


Posted

in

,

by

Tags:

Comments

7 responses to “Is Trump’s Order to End DEI Conservative?”

  1. Michael Brazier Avatar
    Michael Brazier

    If the criterion for knowledge is that there’s nobody who will regard being told to assert it as an imposition on their liberty, then there’s nothing whatsoever we can call “knowledge” – not when, for instance, the proposition that sex is a biological trait has been denied in all seriousness. So you need to explain how to reach “objective certainty” and thus knowledge.
    And I don’t know of any systematic metaphysics that doesn’t either A) put “God exists” in the class of propositions that are objectively certain or B) exclude propositions that we really need to be in that class, like “water freezes at 0 degrees Celsius”. Locke’s metaphysics, for example, is a clear example of B). If classic liberalism has to thread that needle to justify itself, it’s in deep trouble, because I doubt it can be done.
    The only way I see to reach something like classic liberalism is to draw the Catholic distinction between natural theology and revealed theology, the former being what’s “available to the searching intellect of any person of good will”; and then to say that, as a purely secular institution, the State can enforce only what follows from natural theology, because the truth of revelation is outside its competence to determine. Unfortunately, the Catechism’s declaration of the purpose of human life is part of natural theology, which puts the atheist out of court. But if you want a State that regards its function as both protective and directive, but doesn’t establish a particular church … is there any other option?

  2. Michael Brazier Avatar
    Michael Brazier

    I may be dense, but I don’t see what those articles have to do with your post, or my comment, or each other.

  3. BV Avatar
    BV

    Michael,
    You are obviously not dense. Those articles are tangentially related to my post. But the main reason I placed those links there was because I wanted to save the articles for reading later. I’ve been busy, but I will try to respond to your comments tomorrow. No promises, though. The ‘hell’ comments are very good and need thinking through.
    Here’s another that I want to read: https://thehill.com/opinion/immigration/5120027-spoiling-for-a-fight-why-challenging-birthright-citizenship-is-a-win-win-for-trump/

  4. BV Avatar
    BV

    >>If the criterion for knowledge is that there’s nobody who will regard being told to assert it as an imposition on their liberty, then there’s nothing whatsoever we can call “knowledge” << Where did I say this?

  5. Michael Brazier Avatar
    Michael Brazier

    You didn’t. You did say this:
    “But is it known, as opposed to reasonably believed, that there is a God, etc.? Most atheists would deny that the proposition in question is even reasonably believed. Bishop Barron’s Catholicism is to their minds just so much medieval superstition. Suppose, however, that the good bishop’s worldview is simply true. That does us no good unless we can know that it is true. Suppose some know (with objective certainty) that it is true. That also does us no good, politically speaking, unless a large majority in a society can agree that we know that it is true.”
    Now that paragraph abruptly changes the subject – it starts with “Do we know that God exists” but then jumps to “Can we convince society at large that God exists”. Suddenly introducing practical considerations into what was, up til then, a discussion of how the American political tradition departs from Catholic social theory is more than a little odd. I honestly supposed that you were saying the fact of atheists objecting to a presumption that God exists being written into the law was, in itself, good reason in principle for the law not to do so.
    Now, that being said – I don’t think Bishop Barron is correct about Locke or Jefferson. Certainly Hobbes thought that the true nature of human happiness was unknowable, but Locke didn’t agree with him there, and Jefferson followed Locke. “The pursuit of happiness” from Jefferson’s pen didn’t mean the pursuit of whatever one happens to want, but the pursuit of what, given human nature, actually does make us happy. Where Jefferson parted ways with Catholic social theory (and with Locke) was his distrust of revealed theology. The view that the law should have no directive function at all (“purely procedural liberalism”) is, so far as I know, an innovation of the 20th century.

Leave a Reply to Michael Brazier Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *