Footnotes to Plato from the foothills of the Superstition Mountains

Geach on Proper Names: Mental Acts Chapter 16

Peter Geach, Mental  Acts, Chapter 16 (RKP, 1957) is eminently relevant to present concerns and quite sensible. Herewith, an interpretive summary. Per usual, I take the ball and run with it.

Geach rejects the Russellian view that ordinary proper names are definite descriptions in disguise, but he also rejects the notion that proper names have no connotation at all. As for the disguised   description view, it is "palpably false" since " . . . when I refer to a person by a proper name, I need not either think of him explicitly in a form expressible by a definite description, or even be prepared  to supply such a description on demand. . ." (pp. 66-67)

This seems correct. Thomas Aquinas once came up in a conversation I had with my unlettered brother-in-law. The latter said something like, "Aquinas was a big name in Catholic theology." My brother-in-law was undoubtedly referring to the same person I was referring to even though he would not have been able to supply even one definite description. Recall that to be definite a description must be of the form, the unique x such that [insert description]. 'A big name in Catholic theology' is an indefinite description.

Geach also provides an interesting critique of Quine's "intransigent" extension of the Russellian line whereby names are transformed into predicates. Thus for Quine 'Pegasus is winged' goes over into   something like 'There is exactly one x such x pegasizes, and x is winged.' Perhaps we will discuss Geach's Quine critique in a separate post.

Geach also rejects the view that ordinary proper names — which, nota bene, are to be distinguished from logically proper names — are devoid of connotation. On this view, "no attributes logically follow from a thing's being given a proper name." (67) Proper names are bestowed by fiat, whence it follows that there is no right or wrong  about the application of a name: there is no property possession of which by a thing is a necessary condition of the name's being attached to it. It is different in the case of a general term. If 'fat' is true of Al, it follows that there is a property in virtue of whose possession by Al the term is correctly applied to him. By contrast, on the view under consideration, we cannot speak of a name being true of its nominatum, or not true of it.

As I said, Geach rejects this theory of names according to which the meaning of a name is exhausted by its reference.  In the typical case, the same name applies to a person throughout his life from infancy to dotage. Geach takes this to imply that "the baby, the youth, the adult, are one and the same man." (69) They are not the same absolutely, or the same thing, but the same man. Here Geach sounds his theme of the sortal-relativity of identity. One cannot say sensibly of two things that they are the same absolutely; what one can say is that they are the same relative to some sortal under which both fall. If  so,

     . . . my application of the proper name is justified only if (e.g.)
     its meaning includes its being applicable to a man and I keep on
     applying it to one and the same man. On this account of proper
     names, there can be a right and wrong about the use of proper
     names. (69)

This jives with what I was saying earlier about 'God.' The notion that 'God' could denote anything at all, whether a sense of fear, a bolt of lightning, or what have you, strikes me as absurd. But that is the consequence one must swallow if one thinks of names as mere external tags devoid of sense. Geach now considers an objection:

     It has often been argued that it cannot be part of the meaning of a
     proper name that its bearer should be a man, because we cannot tell
     this by hearing the name, and because there is nothing to stop us
     from giving the same name to a dog or a mountain. You might as well
     argue that it cannot be part of the meaning of 'beetle' that what
     it is applied to must be an insect, because we cannot learn this
     meaning just from the sound of the words, and because 'beetle' is
     also used for a sort of mallet. In a given context, the sense of
     'beetle' does include: being an insect, and the sense of
     'Churchill' does include: being a man. (70)

What Geach is saying here contradicts what our friend Edward maintains, namely, that ordinary proper names are tags whose meaning is exhausted by their reference.  Suppose a one-eared rabbit wanders into my yard  and I give it the name 'Gulky.'  Just before the moment of baptism, the arbitrary sound 'Gulky' has no meaning at all.  At the moment of baptism, it acquires a meaning which is its referent.  Now suppose the rabbit wanders off and a coyote comes into the yard and I  say, 'There's Gulky again.'   You say,'That's not Gulky, Gulky's a rabbit!'  The point here is that once 'Gulky' is introduced as a name for a particular rabbit, it acquires not only a referent but also the connotation rabbit-name, a connotation that prevents me from applying that name to anything other than a rabbit.

And then one day the coyote kills Gulky. Does 'Gulky' cease to be a rabbit-name and go back to being a meaningless sound? 

As Geach says, there can be a right and wrong about the use of a proper name.  Having introduced 'Gulky' as the name of a rabbit, I misuse that name if I apply it to a coyote.  But if proper names are tags whose meaning is exhausted by their reference, then this would not be a misuse at all.  Ergo, etc.

 My point is that this is a non sequitur:

1. Reference of proper names is direct, i.e., not routed through sense.
Therefore
2. The meaning of a proper name is exhausted by its reference.  
 


Posted

in

by

Tags:

Comments

2 responses to “Geach on Proper Names: Mental Acts Chapter 16”

  1. Edward the Ockhamist Avatar

    1. We should distinguish what Frege (?) calls ‘tone’ – any semantic property which is not relevant to truth or falsity. Thus ‘Alice [Cooper] is a man’ is true, and so the name ‘Alice’ does not impact its truth. But it ‘sounds’ odd, i.e. ‘tone’. If I begin the sentence ‘Alice is a ….’ you may certainly have some image of a female in your mind. You may be surprised by the predicate ‘man’. But for logic, semantics is only relevant to truth and falsity. Older readers of this blog may remember ‘a man called Sue’.
    2. You misrepresent my position somewhat when you say “our friend Edward maintains … that ordinary proper names are tags whose meaning is exhausted by their reference”.
    I hold an ‘austere’ or ‘sparse’ theory of singular meaning, in that I aim to explain the meaning of an expression by using that very expression, or a close counterpart of it, in the object language. (Think Tarski). Thus I explain the meaning of ‘Frodo’ by the sentence “’Frodo’ means Frodo”. In this sense, and in this sense only “meaning is exhausted by reference”. I do not hold a ‘tag’ theory in the sense that I hold that the ‘tag’ is a tag of something, for reasons explained in my comment on your post above. “’Frodo’ means Frodo” does not imply “There is something such ’Frodo’ means it”. Nor do I hold that the meaning of ’Frodo’ = Frodo, for that would imply that Frodo is something. But he isn’t. I hold that a proper name – including fictional names – cannot be defined in the sense of decomposing or analysing them into less complex items or elements. Nor do I hold any ‘baptismal’ theory according to which a name acquires significance by being imposed upon some extramental object. We merely say “Once upon a time there was a hobbit called ‘Frodo’”, and we have a ready-to-use singular meaning. Since there is no such object as Frodo, there is no such object to be baptised.

  2. David Brightly Avatar

    Couldn’t someone of Ockham’s minimalist view on proper names accommodate some of what Geach says?
    Once a name has been bestowed on an individual and accepted by a community of speakers there is clearly right and wrong with regard to its use. We are all aware of the confusions that can arise when two or more individuals are referred to by a single name. Nevertheless, before a (simple) name is bestowed there need be nothing about the word itself that requires it to name a particular sort. A made-up name will have no connotation and there will be no right or wrong as to its application.
    A proper name, once bestowed, may come to acquire the connotation of some sort and we may feel it behoves us not to bestow the name on an individual of another sort. But surely we feel just as obliged not to bestow the name on another individual of the same sort. It’s ambiguity of referent that we seek to avoid. Merely avoiding ambiguity of connotation doesn’t give us what we want.
    >>As Geach says, there can be a right and wrong about the use of a proper name.  Having introduced ‘Gulky’ as the name of a rabbit, I misuse that name if I apply it to a coyote.  But if proper names are tags whose meaning is exhausted by their reference, then this would not be a misuse at all.  Ergo, etc.<< It's hard to say quite what is wrong with this argument. It strikes me as a rhetorical challenge: If proper names bear no connotation of sort how do you explain that applying the same name to individuals of distinct sorts is a misuse? The minimalist can reply that sorts are irrelevant. Merley applying the same name to two distinct individuals is a misuse.

Leave a Reply to Edward the Ockhamist Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *