Blogging has been good to me. I have met a number of very interesting and intellectually stimulating characters via the blogosphere. I had breakfast with four of them last Sunday morning: Peter L., Mike V., Carolyn M. and Seldom Seen Slim. Topics included logic and existence, the concept of sin, the question why be moral, and the distinction between being guilty and being found guilty in a court of law.
Slim and I found ourselves in that dialectical situation known as a disputation or dispute. Douglas N. Walton, a noted writer on informal logic, defines the term as follows. "A dispute is a dialogue in which one side affirms a certain proposition and the other side affirms the opposite (negation) of that proposition." (Informal Logic: A Handbook for Critical Argumentation, Cambridge UP, 2007, p. 60.) I affirmed the proposition that to be found guilty/not guilty in a court of law is not the same as to be guilty/not guilty. Slim affirmed the negation, namely, that to be found guilty/not guilty is the same as to be guilty/not guilty. The distinction strikes me a self-evident; but Slim denied it and I could not budge him from his position.
While thinking further about the matter yesterday, the following argument occurred to me which strikes me as decisive.
Here are two questions we can ask with respect to burden-of-proof (BOP) considerations as they figure in our legal system. First, why is a BOP assigned at all? (One can imagine courtroom proceedings in which no BOP is assigned.) Second, why is it assigned to the prosecutor/plaintiff? Part of the answer to the first question is because a decision must be made, a question resolved, a dispute adjudicated — and in a timely manner. If there is no presumption on one side or the other, or, correlatively, no BOP assigned to the other side or the one, then in cases where the evidence is evenly balanced or unclear a decision might be not be achievable in a reasonable time. But why lay the BOP on the state or the plaintiff or their respective representatives? At least part of the answer to this second question is that we collectively judge it to be better that a guilty person go free than that an innocent person be wrongly convicted.
Now if Slim grants me this obvious point, then I have all I need to refute his assertion. To prefer that a guilty man go free than that an innocent man be penalized and in some cases executed is precisely to presuppose my distinction between being guilty/not guilty and being found guilty/not guilty in a court of law. He who denies this distinction removes the main reason for the presumption of innocence, a central pillar of our legal system.
Apparently, Slim thinks there is no objective fact of the matter as to whether or not a person accused of a crime is guilty of it or not. He seems to think that a guilty verdict or an acquittal is what makes one either guilty or not guilty. To my mind this is utterly preposterous. It elides the obvious distinction between a fallible judgment about the way things are and the way things are.
My point goes through even if there is no distinction betweem morality and legality. Suppose there is no distinction between a morally wrong killing of a human being and a legally wrong killing of a human being, that the former collapses into the latter. (Someone who holds this could argue that abortion is legal and so ipso facto moral.) Even so, either Jones killed Smith in a legally proscribed manner or he did not — regardless of a court's verdict. There are hard facts about what the law proscribes, and there are hard facts about Jones' behavior in relation to Smith. Those two sets of fact taken together determine whether he is guilty or not guilty.
There is only one way I can imagine my distinction collapsing. In the divine court, if such there be, there cannot be any discrepancy between being found guilty and being guilty, nor between being found innocent and being innocent. The distinction would hold only on the intensional plane; extensionally there would be no possibility of a person beng found guilty/not guilty and being guilty/not guilty. Here below, however, we are stuck with fallible courts. And it is a curious form of idolatry to suppose that our fallible courts can do what only the divine court can do.
Leave a Reply