BV said:
I will now pose a problem for the view that assertion = proposition. Suppose I give the following valid argument, an instance of modus ponens. By 'give an argument,' I mean that I assert its premises, and I assert its conclusion as following from the premises, and this in the presence of one or more interlocutors. Thus the argument is to be taken in concreto, not in abstracto.
If Tom is drunk, then Tom ought not drive
Tom is drunk
—–
Tom ought not drive.
If the argument is valid, as it plainly is, then, in both of its occurrences, the sentence 'Tom is drunk' must express the same proposition. But this cannot be the case if a proposition is identical to an assertion. For the proposition Tom is drunk occurs unasserted in the major, but asserted in the minor. (To assert a conditional is not thereby to assert either its antecedent or its consequent.) Since one and the same proposition can occur unasserted in one context and asserted in another, we must distinguish between a proposition and an assertion.
The Ostrich responds:
I deny that the sentence ‘Tom is drunk’ in the major expresses a proposition at all. It expresses a proposition in the minor, I agree. I also claim that both sentences must have the same content in major and minor. But having the same content is not the same as expressing the same proposition. Perhaps we should rewrite the major as follows:
That Tom is drunk implies that Tom ought not drive.
We connect a name for contents, using a that-clause, with the connector ‘entails’. Thus we express the whole argument as follows
It is the case (that Tom is drunk implies that Tom ought not drive)
It is the case that Tom is drunk
It is the case that Tom ought not drive.
BV counter-responds:
The Ostrich carelessly leaves out the parentheses in the minor and in the conclusion of his re-write of the original argument. His re-write should look like this:
It is the case (that Tom is drunk implies that Tom ought not drive)
It is the case (that Tom is drunk)
It is the case (that Tom ought not drive).
'That Tom is drunk' is not a sentence but a nominal phrase. In the major, it names a proposition, the proposition expressed in English by a tokening of 'Tom is drunk.' It has to name a proposition because the implication relation connects propositions to propositions. In the minor 'that Tom is drunk' also expresses a proposition. It has to if the argument is to be valid.
So one and the same proposition — the one named by 'that Tom is drunk' — occurs in both the major and the minor. It is just that in the major it is not asserted, whereas in the minor it is. Therefore, a proposition is not the same as an assertion — which was my claim all along. (Not original with me, of course. From Frege via Peter Geach.)
So the Ostrich re-write is useless rigmarole. Consider the following re-write:
That Tom is drunk implies that Tom ought not drive
Tom is drunk
Tom ought not drive.
This is valid. In the major, 'That Tom is drunk' names but does not assert a proposition. In the minor 'Tom is drunk' asserts the very same proposition. So one and the same proposition can be both asserted and left unasserted. Therefore, a proposition is not the same as an assertion.
The Ostrich tells us, "But having the same content is not the same as expressing the same proposition." I don't understand that. A content in this context just is a proposition.
Leave a Reply