The Emperor’s Clothes Revisited or Trope Theory Interrogated

The following is a comment by Eric Levy in a recent trope thread.  My responses are in blue.

………………………

Might I revert to the problem of compresent tropes constituting a concrete particular? Heil well formulates it: “One difficulty is in understanding properties as parts that add up to objects” (2015, 120). The whole business seems to me riddled with equivocation, epitomized by Maurin’s formulation: “. . . tropes are by their nature such that they can be adequately categorized both as a kind of property and as a kind of substance.”

BV:  We agree, I think, that standard trope theory is trope bundle theory, a one-category ontology.  This version of the theory alone is presently under discussion.  John Heil puts his finger on a very serious difficulty.  I would add that it is a difficulty not only for trope bundle theory but for every bundle theory including the theory that ordinary particular are bundles or clusters of universals, as well as for Hector Castaneda's bundle-bundle theory.  On Castaneda's theory, an ordinary particular at a time is a synchronic bundle of "consubstantiated" "guises" with a particular over time being a "transubstantiated" diachronic bundle of these synchronic bundles.

Intellectual honesty requires me to say that the theory I advance in PTE also faces Heil's difficulty.  For on the view developed in PTE, ordinary concrete particulars are facts or states of affairs along Bergmannian-Armstrongian lines.  On this theory Socrates is not a bundle but a concrete truth-making fact which has among its ontological constituents or parts his properties.

Generalizing, we can say that the difficulty Heil mentions is one for any constituent ontology that assays properties as ontological parts of the things that, as we say in the vernacular, 'have them.'

Anna-Sofia Maurin is entirely right in her explanation of trope theory but as far as I know she would not admit that Heil's difficulty really is one.

For example, on the one hand, properties are immaterial and interpenetrable abstracta. On the other hand, these immaterial and interpenetrable abstracta somehow constitute, through compresence, an enmattered, impenetrable object. Let us consider a red rubber ball and then a bronze statue. There is the rubber ball – the triumphant consequence of compresent tropes. One trope is to be construed, as we earlier agreed, as an appropriately extended red or redness. Another trope is to be construed as an appropriately diametered spherical contour. Another trope – the hardness trope – is to be construed as an appropriately calibrated resistance to deformation. But then we reach the rubber trope; for we are talking about a red rubber ball. What are we to posit here: an amorphous chunk of rubber appropriately qualified by its compresent fellows? How does trope theory account for the rubber in the red rubber ball?

BV:  Excellent question(s), Eric.  Well, the chunk or hunk of rubber cannot be amorphous — formless — for then it would be materia prima rather than what it is, materia signata.  It is after all a hunk of rubber, not of clay, and indeed a particular hunk of rubber, not rubber in general.  The parcel of rubber is formed matter, hence not prime matter.  It is this matter, not matter in general.  Your question, I take it, is whether this rubber could be construed as a trope in the way that this redness and  this hardness can be construed as tropes.  The latter are simple property particulars.  But this rubber is not simple, but a hylomorphic compound.  So it would appear that this rubber cannot be construed as a trope.

Even if the property of  being rubbery could be construed as a trope, it is hard to see how the stuff, rubber, could be construed as a trope.  For tropes are simple while stuffs are hylomorphic compounds — prime stuff aside.  Tropes are formal or akin to forms while stuffs are matter-form compounds.  Mud is muddy.  But the muddiness of a glob of mud would seem to be quite different from the  stuff, mud.  

My desk is wooden.  The property of being wooden is different from the designated matter (materia signata) that has the form of a desk.  Harry is hairy.  He has hair on his back, in his nose, and everywhere else.  He is one hairy dude.   His hair is literally a part of him, a physical part.  His being hairy, however, is a property of him.  If this property is a trope, then it is (i) a property particular that is (ii) an ontological part of Harry.  But then what is the relation between the ontological part and the physical part?  Can a clear sense be attached to 'ontological part'?   As has often been noted, ontological parts are not parts in the sense of mereology.

Here  then is one question for the trope theorist:  How do you account for the designated matter of a material thing?  Is it a trope or not?   How could a trope theorist deal with matter?  A trope theorist might say this.  "There is no matter ultimately speaking.  It is form 'all the way down.'  A hunk of rubber is not formed matter.  For this matter is either prime matter, which cannot exist, or just a lower level of form."

A second question:  if tropes are immaterial, how can bundling them 'add up' to a material thing? A trope theorist might respond as follows. 

You are assuming that there are in ultimate reality irreducibly material things.  On trope theory, however, material things reduce to systems of compresent tropes.  So, while individual tropes are immaterial, a system of compresent tropes is material in the only sense that stands up to scrutiny.  We trope theorists are not denying that there are material things, we are telling you what they are, namely, bundles of compresent tropes.  Material things are just bundles of immaterial tropes.  The distinction between the immaterial and the material is accommodated by the distinction between unbundled and bundled tropes.  And while it is true that individual tropes interpenetrate, that is consistent with the impenetrability of trope bundles.  Impenetrability is perhaps an emergent feature of trope bundles.

Now let’s move to the bronze statue. What does trope theory do with the bronze? This is, after all, a bronze statue. Is bronze, then, a trope or “property particular” of the statue? And if so, how are we to construe this trope? Is it material or immaterial?

BV:  A trope theorist might be able to say that there are two trope bundles here, the lump of bronze and the statue.  Lump and Statue are arguably two, not one, in that they have different persistence conditions.  Lump exists at times when Statue doesn't.  So they are temporally discernible.  They are also modally discernible.  Even if in the actual world Lump and Statue exist at all the same times, there are possible worlds in which Lump exists but Statue does not. (Of course there are no possible worlds in which Statue exists and Lump does not.)

And to what do we assign the trope of shape: the bronze or the statue? As Lowe point out, “the bronze and the statue, while the former composes the latter, are exactly the same shape. Do they, then, have numerically distinct but exactly coinciding shapes . . .” (1998, 198)? Or does the shape as form pertain to just one candidate? Lowe suggests that the shape, as form, belongs or pertains to the statue, not the bronze, and that the property concerned is “the property of being a statue of such-and-such a shape,” not the property of the statue’s particular shape. The reason for this distinction is that the form (being a statue of such-and-such a shape) is identified with the statue itself.

In this example, in the context of trope theory, how can there be a property, “being a statue of such-and-such a shape,” when the statue itself is constituted? Trope theory cannot account for this property, because trope theory cannot distinguish between the shape of the bronze and the shape of the statue. It cannot make this distinction because, as you point out in PTE, in trope theory there is no distinction between compresence and the existence of the object (Vallicella 2002, 87). One of the tropes in that compresence can be a shape trope, of course. But it cannot be the trope of “being a statue of such-and-such a shape,” because, in the wacky world of trope theory, the statue itself must be constituted before it can be a statue of such-and-such a shape. In other words, no trope in the compresent bundle can be the trope of “being a statue of such-and-such a shape,” because, until the tropes compresent, there cannot be a statue. This is what happens in a one-category ontology that recognizes only property particulars. If there were a trope of “being a statue of such-and-such a shape,” it would have to qualify the statue after the statue had been constituted.

BV:  The last stretch of argumentation is not clear to me.  Please clarify in the ComBox.

Senses of ‘Abstract’ with a Little Help from Hegel

For Eric Levy, who 'inspired' me to dig deeper into this material.

…………………………………

Keith Campbell and others call tropes abstract particulars.  But what is it for something to be abstract?  It may be useful to sort out the different senses of 'abstract' since this term and its opposite 'concrete' are thrown around quite a lot in philosophy.  I propose that we distinguish between ontic and epistemic uses of the word. 

Ontic Senses of 'Abstract'

a. Non-spatio-temporal.  The prevalent sense of 'abstract' in the Anglosphere is:  not located in space or in time.  Candidates for abstract status in this sense: sets, numbers, propositions, unexemplified universals.  The set of prime numbers less than 10 is nowhere to be found in space for the simple reason that it is not in space.    If you say it is, then tell me where it is. The same holds for all sets as sets are understood in set theory.   (My chess set is not a set in this sense.)  Nor are sets in time, although this is less clear: one could argue that they, or rather some of them, are omnitemporal, that they exist at every time. That {1, 3, 5, 7, 9} should exist at some times but not others smacks of absurdity, but it doesn't sound absurd to say that this set  exists at all times. 

This wrinkle notwithstanding, sets are among the candidates for abstract status in the (a) sense.

The same goes for numbers.  They are non-spatio-temporal.

If you understand a proposition to be the Fregean sense of a declarative sentence from which all indexical elements, including tenses of verbs, have been extruded, then propositions so understood are candidates for abstract status in sense (a).

Suppose perfect justice is a universal and suppose there is no God. Then perfect justice is an unexemplified universal.  If there are unexemplified universals, then they are abstract in the (a) sense.

This (a) criterion implies that God is an abstract object.  For God, as classically conceived, is not in space or in time, and this despite the divine omnipresence.  But surely there is a huge different between God who acts, even if, as impassible, he cannot be acted upon, and sets, numbers, propositions and the like that are incapable of either acting or being acted upon.  And so we are led to a second understanding of 'abstract' as that which is:

b. Causally inert.  Much of what is abstract in the (a) sense will be causally inert and thus abstract in the (b) sense.  And vice versa.  My cat can bite me, but the set having him as its sole member cannot bite me.  Nor can I bite this singleton or toss it across the room, as I can the cat.  Sets are abstract  in that they cannot act or be acted upon.  A less robust way of putting it:  Sets cannot be the terms of causal relations.  This formulation is neutral on the question whether causation involves agency in any sense. 

God and Kantian noumenal agents show that the first two criteria come apart.  God is abstract in the (a) sense but not in the (b) sense.  The same goes for noumenal agents which, as noumenal, are not in space or time, but which, as agents are capable of initiating causal event-sequences. 

It may also be that there are items that are causally inert but located in space and time.  (Spatio-temporal positions perhaps?)

So perhaps we should spring for a disjunctive criterion according to which the abstract is that which is:

c. Non-spatio-temporal or causally inert.  This would imply that God and Socrates are both concrete.

d. On a fourth construal of 'abstract'  an item is abstract just in case it is incomplete.  To get a sense of what I am driving at, consider the following from Hegel's essay Who Thinks Abstractly?

A murderer is led to the place of execution. For the common populace he is nothing but a murderer. Ladies perhaps remark that he is a strong, handsome, interesting man. The populace finds this remark terrible: What? A murderer handsome? How can one think so wickedly and call a murderer handsome . . . .

This is abstract thinking: to see nothing in the murderer except the abstract fact that he is a murderer, and to annul all other human essence in him with this simple quality.

The murderer is not just a murderer; he is other things besides: a father, a son, a husband, a handsome devil, a lover of dogs, a strong chess player . . . .  In general, the being of anything that actually exists cannot be reduced to one of its qualities.  To acquiesce in such a reduction is to think abstractly: it is to abstract from the full reality of thing in order to focus on one of its determinations.  But here we should distinguish between legitimate abstraction and vicious abstraction.  What Hegel is railing against is vicious abstraction.

HegelNow I am not interested here in explaining Hegel.  I am using him for my purposes, one of which is to pin down a classical as opposed to a Quinean sense of 'abstract.'  Accordingly, an abstract entity in the (d) sense   is an entity that is got before the mind by an act of abstraction.  But please note that if epistemic access to an entity is via abstraction, it does not follow that the entity is a merely intentional object.  What I am trying to articulate is a fourth ontic sense of 'abstract,' not an epistemic/doxastic/intentional sense.  It could well be that there are incomplete entities, where an entity is anything that exists.  (As I use 'item,' an item may or may not exist, so as not to beg the question against the great Austrian philosopher Alexius von Meinong.)

We have now arrived at the sense of 'abstract' relevant to trope theory.  Here is a red round spot on a white piece of paper.  When I direct my eyes to the spot I see red, a particular shade of red.  That is a datum.  On the trope theory, the red that I see is a particular, an unrepeatable item.  It is not a universal, a repeatable item.  Thus on trope theory the red I see is numerically distinct from the red I see when I look at a numerically different spot of the same (exact shade of ) color. 

It is important to realize that one cannot resolve the question whether properties are particulars or universals phenomenologically.  That I see red here and also over there does not show that there are two rednesses.  For the phenomenological datum is consistent with redness being a universal that is located into two different places and visible in two different places.  Phenomenology alone won't cut it in philosophy; we need dialectics too.  Husserl take note!

There are philosophers who are not bundle theorists who speak of tropes.  C. B. Martin is one.  I do not approve of their hijacking of 'trope,' a term introduced by D. C. Williams, bundle theorist.  I am a bit of a prick when to comes to language.  Technical words and phrases ought to be used with close attention to their provenience.  It rankles me when 'bare particular' is used any old way when it is a terminus technicus introduced by Gustav Bergmann with a precise meaning.  Read Bergmann, and then sling 'bare particular.'

On standard trope theory, trope bundle theory, the spot — a concrete item — is a system of compresent tropes. It is just a bundle of tropes. There is no substratum that supports the tropes: the spot just is compresent tropes.  Furthermore, the existence of the spot is just the compresence of its tropes.  Since the spot exists contingently, the tropes are compresent contingently.  That implies that the compresent tropes can in some sense 'be' without being bundled.  (Note that tropes are bundled iff they are compresent.)  For if there were no sense in which the tropes could 'be' without being bundled, then how could one account for the contingency of a give trope bundle? 

Now if tropes can be without being bundled, then they are not products of abstraction:  they are not merely intentional items that arise before our minds when we abstract from the other features of a thing.  When I consider the redness of the spot, I leave out of consideration the roundness.  On trope theory this particular redness  really exists whether or not I bring it before my mind by a process of abstraction.  Tropes are thus incomplete entities, not incomplete intentional objects.  They are in no way mind-dependent.  They have to be entities if they are to be the ultimate ontological building blocks of ordinary concrete particulars such as our  round, red spot.

An abstract item in the (d) sense, then, is an incomplete entity.  It is not complete, i.e.,  completely determinate.  For example, a redness trope is a a property assayed as a particular.  It is the ontological ground of the datanic redness of our spot and it is this by being itself red.  Our redness trope is itself red. But that is all it is: it is just red.  This is why it is abstract in the (d) sense.  Nothing can be concrete if it is just red.  For if a concretum is red, then it is either sticky or non-sticky (by the Law of Excluded Middle) and either way a concrete red thing is either red sticky thing or a red non-sticky thing.

The Epistemic Sense of 'Abstract'

I have already alluded to this sense according to which an item is abstract iff it is brought before the mind by an act of abstraction and is only as a merely intentional object.

At this point I must take issue with my esteemed coworker in these ontological vineyards, J. P. Moreland.  He writes, ". . . Campbell follows the moderate nominalist tendency of treating 'abstract' as an epistemic, and not ontological, notion." (Universals, p. 53)  I don't think so.  The process of abstracting is epistemic, but not that which is brought before the mind by this process.  So I say that 'abstract' as Campbell uses it is an ontological or ontic notion.  After all, tropes or abstract particulars as Campbell calls them are not mere products of mental abstraction: they are mind-independent building blocks of everything including things that existed long before minds made the scene.

A Waste of a Good Hyphen

A reader doesn't get the point of my earlier entry:

Use-Mention Confusion

Dennis Miller:  "Melissa Harris-Perry is a waste of a good hyphen."

So let me explain it.  Miller is a brilliant conservative comedian who appears regularly on The O'Reilly Factor.  If you catch every one of Miller's allusions and can follow his rap you are very sharp indeed.  He has contempt for flaming leftists like Harris-Perry. Realizing that the Left's Alinskyite tactics need to be turned against them, and that mockery and derision can be very effective political weapons, he took a nasty but brilliant jab at her in the above-quoted line.

What makes the jab comical is Miller's willful confusion of the use and mention of expressions, one class of which is the proper name. One USES the name 'Melissa Harris-Perry' to refer to the person in question.  This person, the bearer of the name, is not a name or any type of expression.  The person in question eats and drinks and fulminates; no name eats and drinks and fulminates. But if I point out that 'Melissa Harris-Perry' is a hyphenated expression, I MENTION the expression; I am talking about it, not about its referent or bearer.  When I say that the name is hyphenated I say something obviously true; if I say or imply  that the woman in question is hyphenated, then I say or imply something that is either necessarily false or else incoherent (because involving a Rylean category mistake) and thus lacking a truth value.  Either way I am not saying anything true let alone obviously true.

But what makes Miller's jab funny?  What in general makes a joke funny?  This question belongs to the philosophy of humor, and I can tell you that it is no joke.  (That itself is a joke, a meta-joke.)  There are three or four going theories of humor.  One of them, the Incongruity Theory, fits many instances of humor.  Suppose you ask me what time it is and I reply:  You mean now?  If I say this in the right way you will laugh.  (If you don't, then, like Achmed the Terrorist, I kill you!) Now what make the joke funny?  It is an instance of incongruity, but I will leave the details for you to work out.  And the same goes for the joke in parentheses.

It is the same with the Miller joke.  Everybody understands implicitly that a name is not the same as its bearer, that some names are hyphenated, and that no human being is hyphenated.  Normal people understand facts like these even if they have never explicitly formulated them.  What Miller does to achieve his comic effect is to violate this implicit understanding.  It is the incongruity of Miller's jab with our normal implicit understanding that generates the humorousness of the situation.

But WHY should it have this effect?  Why should incongruity be perceived by us as funny?  Perhaps I can get away with saying that this is just the way things are.  Explanations must end somewhere.

Am I a pedant or what?

But I am not done.    

There is also a moral question.  Isn't there something morally shabby about mocking a person's name and making jokes at his expense? Some years back I was taken aback when Michael Reagan referred to George Stephanopolous on the air as George Step-on-all-of-us.  A gratuitous cheap-shot, I thought.

But given how willfully stupid and destructive Harris-Perry is, and given that politics is war by another name, is there not a case for using the Left's Alinksyite tactics against them?  (Is this a rhetorical question or am I really asking?  I'm not sure myself.)

Here is a bit of evidence that Harris-Perry really is a a willfully stupid, destructive race-baiter.  There is another in the first entry referenced below.

Anchorage in the Certain

We should anchor our thought in that which is most certain: the fact of change, the nearness of death, that things exist, that one is conscious, that one can say 'I' and mean it, the fact of conscience.  But man does not meditate on the certain; he chases after the uncertain and ephemeral: name and fame, power and position, longevity and progeny, loot and land, pleasure and comfort.

Wealth is not certain, but the grave is.  So meditate on death, asking: Who dies? Who survives? What is death? Who am I? What am I?

Death is certain, but the when is uncertain.  Do not try to make a certainty out of what is uncertain, or an uncertainty out of what is certain.

"What is your life? You are a mist that appears for a little while and then vanishes." (James 4:14)

Against the Lunatic Left

Does it do any good to keep pointing out the obvious, namely, that liberal-left scum have taken over the country and are destroying it?  We can't seem to do anything about it.  Who will stop the rot?  Not establishment Republicans who go along to get along.

Trump?  Are you serious?  There was a point at which I thought Trump might be the man, despite all his glaring defects.  But no longer.  He had a shot at the presidency.  But he's blown it:   his judgment is so bad, or his ego is so huge, that he cannot control his tongue. He possesses an excess of groundless self-confidence, just like Obama.  (And like Obama, he is a liar and a bullshitter.)  Trump thinks he can just 'wing it' without doing any real work or learning anything about the issues.  Thus he thinks he can enter the snake pit with a slimy leftist like Chris Matthews and escape unharmed without having done any real preparation. 

As for the existence of leftist rot, here (HT: Bill Keezer) is a taste of The Diplomad:

Continue reading “Against the Lunatic Left”

My One Claim to Chess Fame: The ‘Famous’ Vallicella Trap in the Caro-Kann

What follows are two posts written by Dennis Monokroussos from his first-rate chess weblog, The Chess Mind.  For purposes of comparison, here are the United States Chess Federation ratings of four, actually five,  chess playing philosopher friends. For detailed stats click on the names.   Dennis Monokroussos: 2385.  Timothy McGrew: 2196.  Victor Reppert: 1912.  Ed Yetman: 1800.  Bill Vallicella: 1543.  (My highest rating was 1726) 
 
Part of my point is that life is unfair.  Why should I have a trap named after me, when nothing chessic is named after my above-listed philosophizing chess betters?  Perhaps it shows that even a patzer can have a good idea now and again.  Why should I get to join Franz Brentano in the annals of chess?  (The Brentano Defense in the Ruy Lopez is named after him: 1. e4 e5 2. Nf3 Nc6 3. Bb5 g5)
 
Am I comparing myself to Brentano?  Well, yes: anything can be compared to anything.
 
If anyone has any idea as to Brentano's playing strength, shoot me an e-mail.
 
…………………………..
 
The Famous Vallicella Trap?! (posted 8 May 2008)

I was browsing IM Jovanka Houska's 2007 book Play the Caro-Kann, and while looking through the introductory section on the Panov/Botvinnik Attack I read something incredible. In a subsection called 7th move sidelines, I came across this:

1 e4 c6 2 d4 d5 3 exd5 cxd5 4 c4 Nf6 5 Nc3

5 Nf3 is known as Vallicella's Caro-Kann trap – Black has to watch out for one big trick. Best is simply to play 5…Nc6, transposing to the main line after 6 Nc3, but 5…Bg4? would be a mistake after 6 c5! Nc6 7 Bb5. The point is that Black has big difficulties defending the c6 point; for example, 7…e6 8 Qa4 Qc7 9 Ne5 Rc8 10 Bf4 and White is winning! [p. 76]

There's nothing objectionable about the analysis*; rather, what struck me was the reference to Vallicella's Caro-Kann trap, as if this was standard lore in treatments of the Caro-Kann. How did Bill Vallicella, an outstanding philosophical blogger but a 1500-1700 club player not engaged in publicizing his games, suddenly achieve such fame? I had come across his trap either from an email by him or on a post on his predominantly philosophical blog, but when did a move he may have played but a single time turn into an idea requiring mention in a pretty major new theoretical work?

Houska doesn't cite a source, and I certainly didn't recall seeing it in any published materials, so naturally it was off to Google. Entering "Vallicella Caro-Kann", I discovered the main source, conveniently entitled "Vallicella's Caro-Kann Trap"…and you can, too – just click here. Then laugh.**

* Actually, while I wouldn't disagree with her positive suggestion, I don't believe 5…Bg4 is in fact a mistake; the real error comes later. After, e.g. 7…e5 I don't see a White advantage after 8.dxe5 Ne4 or 8.Qa4 Bxf3 9.Bxc6+ bxc6 10.Qxc6+ Nd7 11.gxf3 exd4, and even the arguably best 8.Nc3 promises little or nothing after 8…Nd7 9.dxe5 Bxf3 (10.Qxf3 d4; 10.gxf3 a6).

** If anyone knows IM Houska personally, please ask her to write me  – I'd like to trace the path from Vallicella's idea to her book.

…………………………

Vallicella's Caro-Kann Trap (posted 27 August 2005)
 
After 1.e4 c6 2.d4 d5 3.exd5 cxd5 4.c4 Nf6, the usual follow-up is 5.Nc3, when Black has three standard replies:

(A) 5…e6, when White plays 6.Nf3,
(B) 5…g6, when White plays 6.Qb3, and
(C) 5…Nc6, when White can either accede to the pin after 6.Nf3 Bg4, or else play the sharper but less reliable 6.Bg5.

Instead, the Maverick Philosopher has been utilizing the tricky 5.Nf3. It looks  slightly clumsy, welcoming the Black bishop to g4 right away, but his idea is revealed after 5…Bg4 6.c5 Nc6 7.Bb5 e6 8.Qa4 Qc7 9.Ne5 Rc8 10.Bf4, when between the pin on c6, the threat of various discoveries involving the Bf4/Ne5/Qc7, and other, lesser but still significant problems with the Black position, White is winning.

Where did Black go wrong? I've already addressed this to some extent in a post on my previous blog, but as the move order examined there was a bit different than what we find in this game, I'll offer some new comments.

First, on move 5, Black can respond with the three normal anti-5.Nc3 options: 5…e6, 5…Nc6, and 5…g6. Should he do so, I don't see any advantage to be had by 5.Nf3, and there is a possible disadvantage. After 5.Nc3 g6, White's best try for an advantage is 6.cxd5 Bg7 7.Qb3 O-O 8.Be2 Nbd7 9.Bf3 Nb6 10.Nge2, but this variation is obviously impossible once White has placed the knight on f3. After 5.Nf3 g6 6.Nc3 Bg7 7.cxd5 O-O 8.Bc4 Nbd7 9.O-O Nb6 10.Bb3 both 10…Nbxd5 and 10…Nfxd5 have scored very well for Black.

Second, after 5.Nf3 Bg4 6.c5 Nc6 7.Bb5, the confrontational 7…e5 seems to give Black equal chances after 8.dxe5 Ne4 9.b4 Be7 10.O-O O-O 11.Bxc6 bxc6 12.Qd3 a5 13.Nd4 Bd7.

Third, as mentioned in my earlier blog post (linked above), after 7…e6 8.Qa4, the pawn sac 8…Bxf3 9.Bxc6+ bxc6 10.Qxc6+ Nd7 11.gxf3 leaves Black some compensation for the pawn in the form of White's numerous pawn weaknesses and the lack of an obvious refuge for the White king.

In sum, I think 5.Nf3 is objectively inferior to 5.Nc3. However, it doesn't seem that much weaker, and it does come with a nice positional trap, making it a reasonable surprise weapon for the odd game.

The variations above, and a bit more, can be replayed here.

Saturday Night at the Oldies: ‘Foolish’ Songs for the Day after April Fool’s Day

I may be a day late and a dollar short, but here for your auditory amusement are some tunes in celebration or bemoanment of human folly the chief instance of which is romantic love.  Who has never been played for a fool by a charming member of the opposite sex?  Old age is the sovereign cure for romantic folly and I sincerely recommend it to the young and foolish.  Take care to get there.

Elvis Presley, A Fool Such as I
Ricky Nelson, Poor Little Fool.  Those "carefree devil eyes" will do it every time. 
Brenda Lee, Fool #1
The Shirelles, Foolish Little Girl
Ricky Nelson, Fools Rush In.  "Fools rush in/Where wise men never go/But wise men never fall in love/So how are they to know?" 
Sam Cooke, Fool's Paradise. Sage advice. 
Elvin Bishop, Fooled Around and Fell in Love
Kingston Trio, Some Fool Made a Soldier of Me
Quicksilver Messenger Service, The Fool
Tony Bennett and Bill Evans, My Foolish Heart
Bill Evans, Foolish Heart
Lesley Gore, She's a Fool
Paul McCartney, The Fool on the Hill

Aretha Franklin, Chain of Fools
Connie Francis, Everybody's Somebody's Fool
Grateful Dead, Ship of Fools
Frank Sinatra, I'm a Fool to Want You 

Chess and Philosophy

In chess, the object of the game is clear, the rules are fixed and indisputable, and there is always a definite outcome (win, lose, or draw) about which no controversy can arise.  In philosophy, the object and the rules are themselves part of what is in play, and there is never an incontrovertible result. 

So I need both of these gifts of the gods.  Chess to recuperate from the uncertainty of philosophy, and philosophy to recuperate from the sterility of chess.

Philosophy and Chess

Both can be utterly absorbing, and yet both can appear in a ridiculous light.  Thus both can appear to be insignificant pursuits far removed from 'reality.'  The difference is that only philosophy can tackle the inevitable question, What is reality?

The denigrator of philosophy himself philosophizes, unlike the denigrator of chess who remains outside chess.

But it usually does no good to point out to the denigrator of philosophy that he presupposes an understanding of reality and thus himself philosophizes in an inarticulate and uncritical way.  For he is too lazy and unserious to profit from the remark:  he does not want truth; he is content to wallow in the shallow opinions he happens to have — and that have him.

Lust versus Pride

Both are deadly to the moral life but they push or pull in opposite directions.  Lust leads to dispersion into sensuous multiplicity.  Pride leads to fixation on the false unity of the ego.  These are two different ways to lose your soul or true self.