On the Enforcing and Permitting of Coreferentiality by Argument-Forms

This argument is invalid:

Cicero was a Roman
Tully was a philosopher
—–
Some Roman was a philosopher.

Quite simply, there is no middle term. The example is an instance of the dreaded quaternio terminorum. But of course we learned at Uncle Willard's knee that Cicero = Tully. Add that fact as a premise and the above argument becomes valid. As a general rule, any invalid argument can be rendered valid by adding one or more premises.

Comments on London Ed’s “Towards a Positive Theory”

 My comments are in blue.

1. Another claim which is nearly Moorean.  I claim that the following argument is valid:

Frodo is a hobbit
Frodo has large feet
Some hobbit has large feet

I am not saying that the premisses are true. Clearly if there are no such things as hobbits, the first sentence has to be false. But it [the argument] is valid. The premisses can't be true and the conclusion false. If there were such a thing as Frodo, and if he was a hobbit, and if he had large feet, it has to be the cases that some hobbit (him) has large feet. So the argument is valid.

[. . .]

2. Assuming the argument above is valid, what fact makes it valid?  I claim that it is a purely semantic property of the proper name 'Frodo'. I.e. it is in virtue of the meaning of 'Frodo' that the premisses cannot be true with the conclusion false. By 'purely semantic', I mean a feature of the term that it continues to possess even though it has no extension, i.e. there is nothing it refers to or denotes.

Stylistic comment: I would strike “continues to possess” and substitute “possesses.” After all it can't be your view that purely fictional names go from having extensions to not having them.

Substantive comment: What you say in #1 above seems correct. But now you take a turn that is reasonably resisted. You want to know what makes the Frodo argument valid. I say it is valid because it has a valid form:

a is F
a is G
ergo
Some F is G.

It is this form that makes it impossible for an argument having this form to have true premises and a false conclusion. It has nothing to do with any semantic property of a substituend of the arbitrary individual constant, 'a.' Whether the subject matter of an argument is fiction or fact makes no difference to its validity or to the explanation of its validity. Logic abstracts from content; hence it treats 'Frodo,' 'Noah,' 'Churchhill' and 'Obama' the same, as substituends of an arbitrary individual constant.

 It is not clear what you are claiming. Are you saying that there is a semantic property that only (purely) fictional names have? And what is this semantic property? Does 'Noah' have it as well?

 Here is one guess at what you might mean. Purely fictional names, as such, do not and cannot have existing referents. Otherwise they wouldn't be purely fictional. Given, as you believe, that (a) the only referents are existing referents, and that (b) there are no modes of existence/being, you seem to be saying that purely fictional names, qua purely fictional names, do not and cannot have referents, full stop. Now if every sentence in which such a name figures is false (as you seem to believe), then there is no argument featuring purely fictional names that has true premises and a false conclusion. Therefore every such argument is by default valid (given the technical definition of validity that we both accept).

Is that what you mean?

If yes, then perhaps the semantic property you are talking about is the propery of necessarily not having a referent. Call this property 'P.' Now is P an intrinsic property of a name like 'Frodo' or is it a relational property? But surely there is no intrinsic property of a name that makes it a purely fictional name, and thus a name necessarily extensionless. What makes a name purely fictional is primarily the intention of the author, and secondarily the intentions of the readers (listeners, etc) who are complicit with the author in the fictional enterprise.

This is not Moorean.  Someone could claim that the argument is valid because 'Frodo',  if meaningful, refers to a non-existing thing, and because it refers to the same non-existing thing in both premisses.  Some arguments against:

Comment: Why do you ignore the simplest and most obvious explanation of validity, the one I gave above?

 (i) The Razor: why posit non-existing things in order to explain a matter of logic, when a semantic explanation would suffice? E.g. we don't need weird entities to explain the validity of 'every bachelor is unmarried, some people are bachelors, some people are unmarried'.

Comment: One problem is that I don't understand what you mean by a semantic explanation of validity. I grant you that the Frodo argument is valid: anyone who argues in accordance with the pattern embodied in that argument argues correctly. But I don't see that this has anything to do with whether the terms in the argument have non-null extensions. A Meinongian will say that 'Frodo is a hobbit' is true. But I am prepared to grant you that the sentence is false. But it doesn't matter since we know from Logic 101 that a valid argument can have false premises and a false conclusion.

 (ii) "Frodo is a hobbit, he has large feet, some hobbit has large feet" is also valid. Do we need strange entities to explain the validity of arguments containing pronouns?

(iii) "Frodo is a hobbit who has large feet, some hobbit has large feet" is also valid. Do we need strange entities to explain the validity of arguments containing the word 'who'?

(iv) "Frodo is a hobbit with large feet, some hobbit has large feet" is also valid. Do we need strange entities to explain this?  (My hunch is that the Meinongian will give up on this point. The onus is then on him to explain the difference between this one and any of the previous ones).

Comment: The validity of each of the variant arguments can be explained in the manner I indicated.

 3. Now for the radical claim: the inferential property above is both necessary and sufficient to explain fictional individuation. Necessary is obvious. If we don't accept the validity, we could suppose that each token of the term 'Frodo' referred to a different character, and thus no two sentences in LOTR was ever about the same character. Clearly no one could understand the story if that were so.  Sufficient is not so obvious, I will not defend that here.

Comment: Now you have really lost me. First of all, what is the inferential property? Presumably you mean that empty names have a property that explains the validity of (all? Some?) of the arguments in which they figure. What property is that? The property of being necessarily extensionless? Then why don't you say that?

And what is fictional individuation? You don't think that Frodo is a genuine individual. If he were, he would be a nonexistent individual and you reject such individuals. So there is no individual, Frodo. But if there is no individual, then there is no question of individuation in either the epistemological or the ontological sense of this term. Presumably, you mean by 'individuate' pick out, single out, identify in a way that supports cross-referencing? You need to explain this.

If this is what you mean, then on your view there is no Frodo to pick out or single out in thought. On your nominalism, all there is is the name. And you can't eke by with that alone. When I think about Frodo, I am not thinking about 'Frodo.' In fact, I can think about Frodo even if I have temporarily forgotten what his name is. Suppose I am thinking about the corpulent side-kick of Don Quixote, but have forgotten his name. I am thinking about Sancho Panza despite my not remembering that his name is 'Sancho Panza.'

Any adequate theory has to distinguish among: empty names, tokenings thereof, and tokenings thereof with understanding. If a voice synthesizer makes the sound associated with 'Frodo,' then the name is tokened, but nothing semantic is going on.

4. The really really radical claim: the semantic feature that explains individuation in fiction also explains individuation 'in reality'.  So radical I won't try to defend it here.  The defence would be roughly on the lines of: the same phenomenon cannot have two different causes. Same effect = same cause, which is a well accepted principle of scientific explanation. Obviously this would require defending that the effect is the same: I won't go into that here. The main pillars of the theory are (1) and (2) above. Inferences involving fictional names are valid, even though the premisses are never true. And the explanation of their validity does not involve Meinongian objects.

Comment: Once again, you haven't told us what individuation is. That word is a piece of philosophical jargon, not of ordinary language. No sentence containing it could count as Moorean. So you have to explain the term. And you have to meet my objection that there cannot be individuation in either the epistemological/semantic or ontological sense if there is no individual. How do you avoid embracing this inconsistent triad:

There are no fictional individuals.
Questions about individuation makes sense only if there are individuals.
Fictional names individuate.

 I should think that your “really really radical claim” is hopeless. There is a huge difference between a genuine individual such as Obama and Frodo. You won't be able to paper over this difference especially since you reject Meinongian individuals and Plantingian haecceity properties.

The Cyberattack on Typepad Continues

This has been going on since Thursday.  There is nothing wrong at my end: the Typepad server is under DDoS attack: Distributed Denial of Service.

Could the malevolence abroad in this world be a merely natural phenomenon? I rather doubt it.  But I'd better post this while I have a window of opportunity.

Dissertation Advice on the Occasion of Kant’s Birthday

                     

Kant-so Immanuel Kant was born on this date in 1724. He died in 1804. My dissertation on Kant, which now lies 36 years in the past, is dated 22 April 1978.  But if, per impossibile, my present self were Doktorvater to my self of 36 years ago, my doctoral thesis might not have been approved! As one's standards rise higher and higher with age and experience one becomes more and more reluctant to submit anything to evaluation let alone publication. One may scribble as before, and even more than before, but with less conviction that one's outpourings deserve being embalmed in printer's ink. (Herein lies a reason to blog.)

So finish the bloody thing now while you are young and cocky and energetic.  Give yourself a year, say, do your absolute best and crank it out. Think of it as a union card. It might not get you a job but then it just might. Don't think of it as a magnum opus or you will never finish. Get it done by age 30 and before accepting a full-time appointment. And all of this before getting married. That, in my opinion, is the optimal order. Dissertation before 30, marriage after 30.  Now raise your glass with me in a toast to Manny on this, his 290th birthday. Sapere aude!

Cartoon borrowed from site of Slobodan Bob Zunjic

The Central Axiom of Partisan Politics

According to Charles Krauthammer (Things That Matter, Crown Forum, 2013, p. 64),

To understand the workings of American politics, you have to understand this fundamental law: Conservatives think liberals are stupid.  Liberals think conservatives are evil.

Robert Paul Wolff unwittingly provides corroboration:

On Easter Sunday, it is only fitting that the reliably despicable Ross Douthat should once again rise from the dead with an incoherently dreadful column on Piketty.  I will not try to summarize it.  As Aristotle observed [I think], shit has no form, and hence cannot easily be apprehended by reason.  You may read it for yourself.  I take Douthat's column as a good sign, a harbinger of Spring.   When the rats on the sinking ship of capitalism pause in their scramble down the hawsers to acknowledge the reemergence of Marx from the dustbin of history [how's that for a mixed metaphor?], there is hope on this annual celebration of resurrection.

Note that Wolff does not address the content of Douthat's essay, though he does have the decency to link to it.  What he does is portray Douthat as a reliably despicable zombie and rat, a shill for capitalism, who has penned an incoherently dreadful column, a piece of shit beneath the apprehension of reason.

Well thank you Professor Wolff for this wonderful Easter Sunday illustration of the Central Axiom and for reminding us once again of how dangerous you leftists are, and, indirectly, how important our Second Amendment rights are.

Typepad Downtime

Sorry if you couldn't get through at various times over the last few days.  The following from the Typepad geeks:

What happened? Beginning Thursday evening, Typepad was hit with a distributed denial of service (DDoS) off and on through today. A DDoS attack is an attempt to make services unavailable . . . . The attack on Typepad was similar to an attack on Basecamp which you can read about here.

 

Holy Saturday Night at the Oldies: Death and Resurrection

Bob Dylan, See that My Grave is Kept Clean

Bob Dylan, In My Time of Dyin'

Bob Dylan, Gospel Plow

Bob Dylan, Fixin' to Die

Johnny Cash, Ain't No Grave

Johnny Cash, Redemption

Johnny Cash, Personal Jesus

Johnny Cash, Hurt

Mississippi John Hurt, You Got to Walk That Lonesome Valley

Edwin Hawkins Singers, Oh Happy Day

Johnny Cash, Final Interview.  He speaks of his faith starting at 5:15.

Ludwig Wittgenstein, Culture and Value, p. 45e: "Go on, believe! It does no harm."

A Problem of Evil for Atheists

Suppose you are an atheist who considers life to be worth living.  You deny God, but affirm life, this life, as it is, here and now.  Suppose you take the fact of evil to tell against the existence of God.  Do you also take the fact of evil to tell against the affirmability of life?  If not, why not?

In this entry I will explain what I take to be one sort of problem of evil for atheists, or rather, for naturalists. (One can be an atheist without being a naturalist, but not vice versa.)  For present purposes, an atheist is one who affirms the nonexistence of God, as God is traditionally conceived, and a naturalist is one who affirms that reality, with the possible exception of so-called abstract objects, is exhausted by space-time-matter.  Naturalism entails atheism, but atheism does not entail naturalism.

Are the following propositions logically consistent?

a. Life is affirmable.

b. Naturalism is true.

c. Evil objectively exists.

1. What it means for life to be affirmable

AuschwitzTo claim that life is affirmable is to  claim that it is reasonable to say 'yes' to it.  Life is affirmed by the vast majority blindly and instinctually, and so can be; in this trivial sense life is of course affirmable.  But I mean 'affirmable' in a non-trivial sense as signifying that life is worthy of affirmation.  This is of course not obvious.  Otherwise there wouldn't be pessimists and anti-natalists.  Let me make this a bit more precise.

To claim that life is affirmable is to maintain that human life has an overall positive value that outweighs the inevitable negatives.  Note the restriction to human life.  I am glad that there are cats, but I am in no position to affirm feline life in the relevant sense of 'affirm': I am not a cat and so I do not know what it is like 'from the inside' to be a cat. 

'Human life' is not to be understood biologically but existentially. What we are concerned with is not an  objective phenomenon in nature, but life as lived and experienced from a subjective center.  So the question is not whether it is better or worse for the physical universe to contain specimens of a certain zoological species, the species h. sapiens.  The question is whether it is on balance a good thing that there is human life as it is subjectively lived from a personal center toward a meaning- and value-laden world of persons and things.  The question is whether it is on balance a good thing that there is human subjectivity.

Life is goodNow it may be that over the course of a particular human life a preponderance of positive noninstrumental good is realized.  But that is consistent with human life in general not being worth living.  If my life turns out to have been worth living, if I can reasonably affirm it on my death bed and pronounce it good on balance, it doesn't follow that human life in general is worth living.  Let us agree that a particular human life is worth living if, over the course of that life, a preponderance of positive noninstrumental value is realized.  To say that positive value preponderates is to say that it outweighs the negative.

The question, then, is whether human life, human subjectivity, in general is affirmable.  To make the question a bit more concrete, and to bring home the point that the question does not concern oneself alone, consider the question of procreation.  To procreate consciously and thoughtfully is to affirm life other than one's own.

Suppose that one's life has been on balance good up to the point of one's procreating.  Should one be party to the coming-into-existence of additional centers of consciousness and self-consciousness when there is no guarantee that their lives will be on balance good, and some chance that their lives will be on balance horrendous?  Would you have children if you knew that they would be tortured to death in the equivalent of Auschwitz?  Note that if a couple has children, then they are directly responsible for the existence of those children; but they are also indirectly responsible in ever diminishing measure for the existence of grandchildren, great grandchildren, etc.  If life is not affirmable, then it is arguable that it is morally wrong to have children, life being a mistake that ought not be perpetuated.  If on the other hand life is affirmable, then, while there might be particular reasons for some people not to have children, there would be no general reason rooted in the nature of things.

2.  Is life affirmable in the face of evil?

More precisely:  Is life affirmable by naturalists given the fact of evil?  There is a problem here if you grant, as I hope you will for the sake of this discussion at least, that natural and moral evils are objective realities.  Thus evil exists and it exists objectively.  It is not an illusion, nor is it subjective.

The question could be put as follows:  Is it rational to ascribe to human life in general an overall positive value, a value sufficient to justify procreation,  given that (i) evil exists and that (ii) naturalism is true? 

If naturalism is true, then there are unredeemed evils.  Let us say that an unredeemed evil is an evil that does not serve a greater good for the person who experiences the evil and is not compensated for or made good in this life or in an afterlife.  Thus the countless lives of those who were born and who died in slavery were lives containing unredeemed evils. In many of these countless cases, there were not only unredeemed evils, but a preponderance of unredeemed evil.  Whatever these sufferers believed, their lives were not worth living.  It would have been better had they never been born.  If naturalism is true, then those sufferers who believed that they would be compensated in the hereafter were just wrong.  Their false beliefs helped them get through their worthless existence but did nothing to make it worthwhile.

Here is an argument from evil for the nonaffirmability of life:

1. Human life in general is affirmable, i.e., possesses an overall positive value sufficient to justify procreation, only if the majority of human subjects led, lead, and will lead, lives which are on balance good.

2. It is not the case (or it is highly improbably that) that the majority of human subjects led, lead, or will lead such lives:  the majority of lives are lives in which unredeemed evil predominates.

Therefore

3. Human life in general is not affirmable, i.e., does not (or probably does not) possess an overall positive value sufficient to justify procreation.

It seems to me that a naturalist who squarely and in full awareness faces the fact of evil ought to be a pessimist and an anti-natalist.  If he is not, then I suspect him of being in denial or else of believing in some progressive 'pie in the future.'   But even if, per impossibile, some progressive utopia were attained in the distant future, it would not redeem the countless injustices of the past. 

Spencer Case Makes his Debut in National Review Online

Long-time friend of and commenter at MavPhil sends me the very good news that he is on board at NRO.   Congratulations, Spencer!  We definitely need more philosophically-trained journalists, and given the corruption and ever-worsening decline of the academic world 'thanks' to leftists, young philosophers like Case do well to consider alternative careers in which they can write and think and preserve their liberty far from the hothouses of political correctness.

Spencer's debut article is Polemics and Philosophy from a British Contrarian, a review of two new books by Roger Scruton, the novel Notes from Underground, and the philosophical work, The Soul of the World.  Case's description of the novel make me want to read it, especially given my visit to Prague last September:

Notes from Underground is mainly set in 1985 in Communist-occupied Prague. Earlier in his career, Scruton covertly visited Prague behind the Iron Curtain, traveling as a lecturer, so the harsh descriptions have an authentic ring to them. Such descriptions allow Scruton to argue against leftist collectivism merely by describing its effects. Sometimes the storyline is coupled with searing polemics, which are most effective when they catch the reader off-guard. For instance, his protagonist observes, “Defenestration is a Czech tradition, the only one that the Communists had retained.”

The story is told in the first person by Jan Reichl, a Czech academic in the United States, who recounts his youth under Communism. Once valued for his past as a dissident writer, he now finds his worth diminishing in the eyes of the academy. Jan writes about his experiences from a meditative distance, full of references to the literature of Kafka, Dostoyevsky, and Zweig, as well as to the music of Schubert and Mahler. The book’s title itself is a reference to Dostoyevsky, whose novella Notes from the Underground is considered one of the first works of existentialist literature. The narrator’s distance from events reduces the emotional immediacy of some scenes, but it also gives the whole story a thoughtful melancholy.

Spencer has some meaty things to say in criticism of Scruton, so I suggest you all head over to  the former's ComBox to register your approbation, disapprobation, congratulations, whatever.  My guess is that he will be evaluated by the NRO editors in part by the length and quality of the comment threads he generates.

Good Friday: At the Mercy of a Little Piece of Iron

Simone Weil, Gravity and Grace, tr. Craufurd, Routledge 1995, p. 75:

The infinite which is in man is at the mercy of a little piece of  iron; such is the human condition; space and time are the cause of  it. It is impossible to handle this piece of iron without suddenly reducing the infinite which is in man to a point on the pointed  part, a point on the handle, at the cost of a harrowing pain. The  whole being is stricken in the instant; there is no place left for God, even in the case of Christ, where the thought of God is not  more at least [at last?] than that of privation. This stage has to  be reached if there is to be incarnation. The whole being becomes privation of God: how can we go beyond? After that there is only the resurrection. To reach this stage the cold touch of naked iron  is necessary.

'My God, my God, why hast thou forsaken me?' There we have the real   proof that Christianity is something divine. (p. 79)

The Fundamental Division in U. S. Politics

George F. Will, drawing upon Timothy Sandefur, maintains that

The fundamental division in U.S. politics is between those who take their bearings from the individual’s right to a capacious, indeed indefinite, realm of freedom, and those whose fundamental value is the right of the majority to have its way in making rules about which specified liberties shall be respected.

[. . .]

The argument is between conservatives who say U.S. politics is basically about a condition, liberty, and progressives who say it is about a process, democracy. Progressives, who consider democracy the  source of liberty, reverse the Founders’ premise, which was: Liberty preexists governments, which, the Declaration says, are legitimate when “instituted” to “secure” natural rights.

Progressives consider, for example, the rights to property and free speech as, in Sandefur’s formulation, “spaces of privacy” that government chooses “to carve out and protect” to the extent that these rights serve democracy. Conservatives believe that liberty, understood as a general absence of interference, and individual rights, which cannot be exhaustively listed, are natural and that governmental restrictions on them must be as few as possible and rigorously justified. Merely invoking the right of a majority to have its way is an insufficient justification.

Is This a Joke?

"Principles of Non-Philosophy is a treatise on the method, axioms and objectives of non-philosophy and represents François Laruelle's mature philosophy." 

That sounds like a joke.  Maybe it is.  With Continental bullshitters you never know.

Here.  Via Andrew Sullivan.  HT: Dave Lull.   I am surprised that NDPR published a review of this book, and an uncritical one at that.

London Ed’s Metaphilosophy

 This from a recent comment by Ed, see article below:

I am starting with a few claims, with the additional claim that the claims are Moorean. Not only do I claim we use fictional or empty names to tell people which individual we are talking about, I claim that this is uncontroversial. Developing a theory to explain the apparent contractions that arise from these Moorean facts is more difficult. But that's the business of philosophy: start with facts that are apparently uncontroversial, move to the contradictions that appear to arise from them, and uncover the hidden assumptions or premisses that lead to the contradictions. Deduce the falsity of the hidden premisses. We have already stumbled across one hidden premiss, hardly noticing it. We agree that the sentence " 'Frodo' refers to Frodo" is relational in form. That's also Moorean. But does it follow that a sentence which is relational in form, really expresses a relation? 

So in overall summary. It is Moorean that there aren't and never were such things as hobbits, and hence never such persons as Frodo, Bilbo, Sam, Smeagol.  But it is also Moorean that at the end of Lord of the Rings, Tolkien tells us which hobbits carried the ring to Mount Doom, and which hobbit fell into the fiery depths of the mountain, carrying the Ring. The rest is philosophy: is there any contradiction buried in these Moorean facts, and if not, how do we explain the appearance of contradiction?

Here is my distillation of Ed's approach:

1. There are certain facts that cannot be reasonably denied.  Call them 'Moorean.'

2. Reflection upon Moorean facts often brings to light certain tensions or problems or apparent contradictions. 

3. The contradictions that arise when we reflect on Moorean data are merely apparent.  Data cannot be contradictory. (Sentences that record data are true, and truths cannot be contradictory.)

4. The merely apparent contradictions derive from hidden assumptions that are not Moorean.

5. The task of philosophy is to solve (dissolve?) the problems by exposing and rejecting the hidden assumptions that give rise to them.

6. The task of philosophy is conservative, not revisionary.  Our ordinary ways of talking and thinking are in order as they stand.   Any problems that arise are due to false assumptions that we bring to the Moorean data.  Apparent inconsistencies that arise when when we reflect upon Moorean data are to be explained away as merely apparent.

To illustrate via an aporetic pentad:

a. 'Frodo' (or a tokening thereof) refers to Frodo.

b. Reference is a dyadic relation.

c. Every relation is such that if one of its terms (relata) exists, then all the others do as well.

d. 'Frodo' (or a tokening thereof) exists.

e. Frodo does not exist. (He is a purely fictional item.)

(a), (d), and (e) are all Moorean or as I say, 'datanic.'  (b) and (c) are in contrast theoretical.  If I understand Ed, he would say that (b) and (c) are the "hidden assumptions" that generate the contradiction in the pentad.  To remove the contradiction, and with it the problem, it suffices to reject one or the other of the theoretical assumptions.

I am pretty sure that Ed will reject (b).  He will not, I am sure, hold to (b) and reject (c) by maintaining that an existent can stand in a genuine relation to a Meinongian nonexistent.  But then Ed owes us an account of what it is for 'Frodo' to refer to or be about Frodo, as opposed to Gandalf, if reference is not a relation.  I suspect that any theory he gives will involve difficulties of its own.

How does my metaphilosophy differ from Ed's? 

Ed seems to think that philosophical problems such as the one embodied in the above pentad are soluble by the exposure and rejection of false assumptions such as (b) above.  There is no need for such exotic posits as Meinongian nonentities or merely intentional objects. Ed seems to think that the task of philosophy is to remove confusions and puzzles that arise when philosophers import false assumptions into the data, thereby causing trouble for themselves.  The Moorean data are unproblematic, and we will come to see this when we sweep aside false theoretical assumptions.

My view is entirely different. The problems are genuine, but they do not have satisfactory solutions.  It is no solution simply to reject (b) above without giving a positive account of what reference or aboutness is.  (b) is not a gratuitous assumption we are making, but a plausibility, despite its not being a Moorean fact.  One cannot simply reject it; one must put something it its place.

So Ed needs to tell us what his positive theory is.  Once he presents it in a form clear enough to be discussed, then I will show why it is unsatisfactory.  And I will do that with every theory that is proposed.  If I am able to pull that off, then I will have given a very good reason to regard the problem as insoluble.