Saturday Night at the Oldies: Spencer’s Picks

Spencer Case thinks I need to expand my musical horizons.  I don't disagree.  He writes,
 
O.K. here are my five picks for good folk/rock music within the last ten years.

First, "The Wrote and the Writ" by Johnny Flynn, an artist I've just discovered. I chose it because of the syncopated guitar and the outstanding lyrics.

Second,  "Right Moves" by Idaho's own Josh Ritter. Ritter been one of my favorites for about six years. He isn't instrumentally out of this world like some of the other artists here, but he's a great songwriter. It's hard to find a representative song for him for a first exposure, but this seems like a safe bet.                                                                                           
Third, "Simple as This" by Jake Bugg, another new discovery. Great lyrics.

Fourth, "Don't Need No" by Punch Brothers. I've seen these guys live and they are  amazing.                                                                        

Fifth, "Big Parade" by Lumineers. These guys are from Denver and actually, they are quite popular now. So not everything on this list is obscure.

 
As far as I'm concerned, these artists prove good music is alive and well, if under-appreciated. Interested to hear how you think they stack up.
 
It's good stuff, Spencer.  I enjoyed 'em all.  Here are some obscure tunes/renditions I think you'll enjoy if you haven't heard them already.  I won't make any invidious comparisons.  It's all good.
 
 
 
 
Ry Cooder, He'll Have to Go
 
Doc Watson, Tom Dooley
 
Nanci Griffith, Boots of Spanish Leather

Kate Wolf and Don Lange, Rock Salt and Nails

Why Would Obama Say He is not Ideological?

Ed Rogers speculates:

The president’s belief that little of what he does is ideologically driven suggests he is living with a pampered, unchallenged mind. He has been told he is so smart for so long that he sees only clarity in his actions and unchallengeable reason in his conclusions. The president’s belief in his own intellect makes him think that whatever he does is simply the only thing a thinking person would do. Nothing ideological about that.

Roger's reading is possible, but not likely.  I incline to  a darker view.  Obama knows that he is a leftist and that leftism is not the only option.  He knows that there are sincere, highly intelligent, principled people who oppose the leftist agenda with an impressive armamentarium of facts and arguments.   Although Obama hangs with his sycophantic own for the most part, he cannot not know about the black conservative Thomas Sowell, for example, and his views.  And given how smart Obama is supposed to be, he will have discerned that Sowell and other black conservatives cannot be dismissed as Uncle Toms.

When Obama said that he is not ideological he was simply lying.  He was stating something he knows to be false with the intent to deceive.

It is right in line with what he said last month:

As soon as I took office, I asked this Congress to send me a recovery plan by President's Day that would put people back to work and put money in their pockets. Not because I believe in bigger government — I don't.

In this example, Obama's mendacity enters the Orwellian.  Opposing bigger government, he is for smaller government.  Bigger government is smaller government. 

The truth is that the man is thoroughly untruthful.  Why does he so brazenly lie, bullshit, prevaricate?  Because he believes that there is nothing wrong with mendacity in the service of a noble cause.  I don't think the man is simply out for his own wealth and power: he sincerely believes in the leftist agenda and that the glorious end justifies and requires the mendacious means.

For this reason he never comes clean about his real goals and values.

If you think about it this way, it all makes sense.  He had to lie again and again about the content of the ACA.  Otherwise it would not have passed.  He knows best what is good for us, and his lies are for our own good.

It’s about Liberty, not Race

 

An Outbreak of Lawlessness: Obama as Dictator

Krauthammer nails it once again.  Excerpt:

What distinguishes an institution from a flash mob is that its rules endure. They can be changed, of course. But only by significant supermajorities. That’s why constitutional changes require two-thirds of both houses plus three-quarters of the states. If we could make constitutional changes by majority vote, there would be no Constitution.

As of today, the Senate effectively has no rules. Congratulations, Harry Reid. Finally, something you will be remembered for.

Barack Obama may be remembered for something similar. His violation of the proper limits of executive power has become breathtaking. It’s not just making recess appointments when the Senate is in session. It’s not just unilaterally imposing a law Congress had refused to pass — the Dream Act — by brazenly suspending large sections of the immigration laws.

We’ve now reached a point where a flailing president, desperate to deflect the opprobrium heaped upon him for the false promise that you could keep your health plan if you wanted to, calls a hasty news conference urging both insurers and the states to reinstate millions of such plans.

Except that he is asking them to break the law. His own law. Under Obamacare, no insurer may issue a policy after 2013 that does not meet the law’s minimum coverage requirements. These plans were canceled because they do not.

The law remains unchanged. The regulations governing that law remain unchanged. Nothing is changed except for a president proposing to unilaterally change his own law from the White House press room.

That’s banana republic stuff, except that there the dictator proclaims from the presidential balcony.

Word of the Day: Depauperate

I stumbled across this word on p. 539 of the heaviest, fattest, stompingest tome in my library, Richard Routley's Exploring Meinong's Jungle and Beyond (Ridgeview, 1980).  The thing is 1,035 pages long.  I could kill a cat with it, and you hope I won't.  A mere $500 for an Amazon used copy. One copy available at the moment. No, I won't sell my copy unless you give me $500,000.00 for it.  Cash on the barrel head.

In this way depauperate objects such as the present king of France can be seen as limiting cases of fictional items . . .

Depauperate

1. Arrested in growth or development; stunted.
2. Severely diminished; impoverished: "But there were no pleasures in Australia. How could my friend admire so paleontologically depauperate a place?" (Jake Page).

Why did the Aussie Routley change his name to 'Sylvan'?  Because of a love of forests? (L. silva, silvae)  Because of a preference for Meinongian jungles over Quinean desert landscapes?

I don't know and it doesn't matter, but this tome does.  I've slogged through most of it over the years.  Very rich, very technical, very good.

Routley Jungle

A Christian Paradox

Man is godlike and therefore proud.  He becomes even more godlike when he humbles himself.

The central thought of Christianity, true or not, is one so repellent to the natural human pride of life that one ought at least to entertain the unlikelihood of its having a merely human origin.  The thought is that God humbled himself to the point of entering the world in the miserably helpless and indigent way we in fact do, inter faeces et urinam, and to the point of leaving it  in the most horrendous way the brutal Romans could devise, and from a most undistinguished spot, a hill  in an obscure desert outpost of their empire.

On Linked-In Invitations

Due to the various Linked-In scams, my policy has been to ignore all invitations.  I received one that appeared to be from a man I know, but when I contacted him, he said he hadn't sent it.  The ways of the scammers are as multifarious as they are devious, so to save time I delete first and ask questions later.

What may appear to be rudeness is really just caution.  It is in the nature of the consevative to be cautious, as it is in the nature of the leftist to be reckless and foolish and to make a mess of things.  Example: Obamacare.

What Problem Does Literary Fiction Pose?

More than one.  Here is one.  And as old Chisholm used to say, you are not philosophizing unless you have a puzzle.  So try on this aporetic triad for size:

1. Purely fictional objects do not exist.

2. There are true  sentences about purely fictional objects, e.g., 'Sherlock Holmes is a detective' and 'Sherlock Holmes is purely fictional.'

3. If a sentence of the form Fa is true, then there exists an x such that 'a' refers to x.

The triad is logically inconsistent: any two limbs entail the negation of the remaining one. So the limbs cannot all be true despite the considerable plausibility of each.  So one of the propositions must be rejected.  But the first is nonnegotiable since it is true by definition.  The leaves two options: reject (2) or reject (3).

Suppose we reject (2).  One way to do this is by supplying a paraphrase in which the apparent reference to the nonexistent is replaced by real reference to the existent.  For example, the apparent reference to Sherlock, who does not exist, is replaced by real reference to a story in which he figures, a story that, of course, exists.  The elliptical approach is one way of implementing this paraphrastic strategy.  Accordingly,

4. Sherlock Holmes is a detective

and

5. Sherlock Holmes is fictional

are elliptical for, respectively,

6. In the Conan Doyle stories, Sherlock Holmes is a detective

and

7. In the Conan Doyle stories, Sherlock Holmes is fictional.

But note that while (5) is plainly true, (7) is plainly false.  So (7) cannot be taken as elliptical for (5) This is a serious problem for the 'story operator' approach.  Or consider the true

8. Sherlock Holmes does not exist.

(8) is surely not short for the false

9. In the Conan Doyle stories, Sherlock Holmes does not exist.

The point can be made with other 'extranuclear' predicates such as 'merely possible' and 'mythological.'  If I say that Pegasus is mythological, I don't mean that, according to legend, Pegasus is mythological.  But the story operator approach also has trouble with 'nuclear' predicates such as 'detective.'  But I'll save that for a subsequent post.

I'll end with a different challenge to the story operator approach.  Consider

10. Pinocchio was less of a liar than Barack Obama.

Whether you consider (1) true or false, it is certainly not elliptical for

11. In Carlo Collodi's The Adventures of Pinocchio (1883), Pinocchio was less of a liar than Barack Obama.

Pinocchio obamaTo put it vaguely, the the trouble with the story operator appoach is that it traps fictional characters within particular stories, songs, legends, tales, etc. so that (i) it becomes difficult to understand how they can show up in different different stories, songs, etc. as they obviously do in the cases of Faust and Pinocchio, and (ii) it becomes difficult to understand how they can show up in comparisons with nonfictional individuals.

 

 

Is Hegel the Protestant Aquinas?

Howard Kainz writes,

It’s a good question. Hegel and Aquinas are certainly comparable in the sense that they treated a wide variety of topics in philosophy and theology, and unified and organized them. Another similarity resides in the prominence of theology in their writings – but with the following caveat: Whereas, in the scholastic approach adopted by Aquinas, philosophy (Aristotelian, Platonic, Stoic, etc.) is the “handmaid of theology,” with Hegel the relationship is inverted: theology becomes the handmaid of philosophy.

It is certainly true that for Aquinas, philosophia ancilla theologiae, "philosophy is the handmaiden of theology," where the theology in question is a reflection on, and systematization of, the data of divine revelation, and not a branch of philosophy.  But it strikes me as not quite right to say that, for Hegel, the relationship is inverted. 

First of all, in what sense is philosophy a handmaiden to theology for Aquinas? Philosophy takes us some distance toward the knowledge of the ultimate truth about the ultimate matters, but not all the way, and not to the truly essential.  It takes us as far as we can go on the basis of experience and discursive reason unaided by revelation  But if we would know the whole truth about the ultimate matters, and indeed the saving truth, then we must accept divine revelation.  We can know that God exists by unaided reason, for example, but not that God is triune.  Thus, for Aquinas, theology supplements and completes what we can know by our own powers.  It neither contradicts the latter, nor does it express it in a more adequate form: it goes beyond it.  A second sense in which philosophy is ancillary to theology is that philosophy supplies the tools of theology, though not its data.  It supplies concepts and argumentative procedures with which the data of revelation can be articulated and organized and shown to be rationally acceptable, a reasoned faith, though not a rationally demonstrable faith.

HegelFor Hegel, however, the content of theology and philosophy are the same; it is just that philosophy expresses this content in an adequate conceptual manner whereas theology expresses it in an inadequate pictorial manner.  To throw some Hegelian jargon, the thinking of theology is vorstellendes Denken; the thinking of philosophy is superior: begriffliches Denken. If Hegel were Aquinas on his head, then Hegel would have to be saying that philosophy brings in new content beyond that of theology.  But that's not his view.  And if Aquinas were Hegel on his head, then Aquinas would have to be saying that the content of philosophy and theology is the same, but that philosophy expresses it inadequately.  And that is not what he is saying.

Hegel clearly subordinates theology to philosophy but it is incorrect to say that, for Hegel, theology is the handmaiden of philosophy in the way that philosophy is the handmaiden of theology for Aquinas.

 This cavil having been lodged, Kainz's piece is a useful little piece of journalism for those who don't know anything about this topic. 

It does annoy  me, however, that  Kainz doesn't supply any references.  For example, we read:

Hegel was critical of Catholicism at times, in his writings and lectures. For example, he once made a scurrilous remark about the Catholic doctrine of the Eucharist . . . .

Very interesting, but what exactly does he say and where does he say it?  Inquiring minds want to know.  Would it have killed Kainz to insert a few references into his piece?  Then a serious dude like me who has almost the whole of Hegel in German and English in his personal library could check the context and amplify his knowledge of the work of the Swabian genius.

Related:  Is Hegel Guilty of 'Epochism'?

Fiction and Alienans Adjectives

David Brightly comments:

As you use them, the terms 'fictional', 'intentional', 'possible', 'incomplete', and others like 'past' have a distinctive effect on the concept terms they qualify. Ordinary adjectives have the effect of narrowing the extension of the concept term they qualify: the red balls are a subset of the balls, the female prime ministers are a subset of the prime ministers, and so on. The terms in question have the opposite effect. They appear to widen, or indeed offset altogether, the extension of the qualified concept. They are thus potent alienating terms. So the question arises, What is the relation (if any) between the concepts 'fictional person' and 'person', between 'intentional object' and 'object', and 'possible X' and 'X'? Ordinary qualification can be uniformly understood in terms of set intersection. Is there a uniform explanation underlying these alienating qualifications?

1.  First of all,  contrary to what David says, there are plenty of ordinary adjectives that do not narrow the extension of the terms they qualify.  There are redundant adjectives, alienans adjectives, and there is the construction known as the contradictio in adiecto. For example, 'decoy' in 'decoy duck' is an ordinary adjective despite its being an alienans adjective; it is just as ordinary as 'female' in 'female duck,' which I call a specifying adjective and which does narrow the extension of the noun 'duck.'   I see no reason to say that specifying adjectives are the only ordinary ones.

2.  We can agree on this:  red balls are a proper subset of balls, and female prime ministers are a proper subset of prime ministers.  We will also agree that round balls are a subset of balls, though not a proper subset, and that female girls are an improper subset of girls. We could say that the last two examples illustrate the null case of specification.  We could make a distinction between properly specifying and improperly specifying adjectives corresponding to the distinction between proper and improper subsets.

3. We can also agree that specificatory qualification (but not all qualification) can be uniformly understood in terms of set intersection if the intersection is non-null.  The set of cats and the set of dogs has an intersection, but it is the null set.  Intersection is defined over all sets, disjoint or not, hence one cannot say that the set of dogs and the set of cats do not intersect.  They intersect all right; it is just that their intersection is empty.  'Canine cat' is an example of a contradictio in adiecto which reflects the fact that the corresponding sets are disjoint.  'Canine' does not specify 'cat.' It does not divide the genus into two species, the canine cats and the non-canine cats.

4. I can't, pace David,  think of an example in which an adjective widens the extension of the term it qualifies.  Can you?   For example, 'former' in 'former wife' does not widen the extension  of 'wife.'  It is not as if there are two kinds or species of wives, former and present.  Tom's former wife is not his wife.   'Former' does not narrow the extension either.  It is an alienans adjective.  It is the same with 'artificial leather.'  Alligator leather and cowshide are two kinds of leather, but artificial and real are not two kinds of leather.

5.  We will agree that all or most the following constructions from ordinary, i.e., non-philosophical English feature alienans adjectives, adjectives that  shift or 'alienate'  or 'other' the sense of the term they qualify: 

  • former wife
  • decoy duck
  • negative growth
  • faux marble
  • ex-priest
  • putative father
  • artificial leather
  • legally dead
  • male chauvinist (on one disambiguation of its syntactic ambiguity; see article below)
  • generational chauvinist (I am a generational chauvinist when it comes to popular music: that of my generation  is superior to that of the immediately preceding and succeding American generations.)
  • quondam inamorata
  • socially contagious (see here)

6.  Note that the adjective in 'alienans adjective' is not alienans!  Note also that 'putative' and 'artificial' function a little differently.  Exercise for the reader: explain the difference and formulate a general test for alienans adjectives.

7.  Observe that  'artificial' in 'artificial insemination' is not an alienans adjective  in that artificial insemination is indeed insemination, albeit by  artificial means. Whatever the means, you are just as pregnant.  So whether an adjective is alienans or not depends on the context.  A false friend is not a friend, but false teeth are teeth. 

8. We now come to more or less controversial examples:

  • same-sex marriage   (Conservative position: same-sex marriage is not marriage)
  • relative truth  (I have a post on this)
  • material implication (see here)
  • epistemically possible
  • derivative intentionality
  • fictional man
  • merely intentional object
  • merely possible animal  ('The chimera is a merely possible animal.')
  • future individual
  • incomplete individual

Is a (purely) fictional man a man? You might be tempted to say yes:  Hamlet is fictional and Hamlet is a man, so Hamlet is a fictional man.  But the drift of what I have been arguing over the last few days is that a fictional man is not a man, and that therefore 'fictional' functions as an alienans adjective.  But I am comfortable with the idea that a merely possible man is a man.  What is the difference?

There might have been a man distinct from every man that  exists.  (Think of the actual world  with all the human beings  in it, n human beings.  There could have been n + 1.) God is contemplating this extra man, and indeed the possible world or maximal consistent state of affairs in which he figures, but hasn't and will not ever actualize him or it.   What God has before his mind is a completely determinate merely possible individual man.  There is only one 'thing' this man lacks: actual existence.  Property-wise, he is fully determinate in respect of essential properties, accidental properties, and relational properties.  Property-wise the merely possible extra man and the actual extra man are exactly the same.  Their quidditative content is identical.  There is no difference in Sosein; the only difference is Sein, and Sosein is indifferent to Sein as Aquinas, Kant, and Meinong would all agree despite their differences.  As Kant famously maintained, Sein is not a quidditative determination, or in his jargon 'reales Praedikat.'

For this reason a merely possible (complete) man is a man.  They are identical in terms of essence or nature or quiddity or Sosein, these terms taken broadly.  If God actualizes the extra man, his so doing does not alter the extra man in any quidditative respect.  Otherwise, he ould not be the same man God had been contemplating.

9.  Brightly hits upon a happy phrase, "alienating qualifications."  In my first bullet list we have examples of alienating qualifications from ordinary English. I expect Brightly will agree with all or most of these examples. His questioin to me is:

Ordinary qualification can be uniformly understood in terms of set intersection. Is there a uniform explanation underlying these alienating qualifications?

If Brightly is looking for a test or criterion I suggest the following:

Let 'FG' be a phrase in which 'F' is an adjective and 'G' a noun.    'F' is alienans if and only if either an FG is not a G, or it does not follow from x's being an FG that x is a G. For example, your former wife is not your wife, a decoy duck is not a duck, artificial leather is not leather, and a relative truth is not a truth. Is an apparent heart attack a heart attack? It may or may not be. One cannot validly move from 'Jones had an apparent heart attack' to 'Jones had a heart attack.' So 'apparent' in 'apparent heart attack'  is alienans.

Now it is obvious that a decoy duck is not a duck, and that a roasted turkey is not a turkey, but the cooked carcass of a turkey; but it is not so obvious that a fictional man is not a man, while a merely possible man is a man.  To establish these  controversial theses — if 'establish' is not too strong a word — requires philosophical inquiry which is of course very difficult and typically inconclusive.  But once we have decided that a certain philosophical phrase is an alienating qualification, then my test above can be applied.