If Boston is Athens, Hopkinton is Marathon

It is Patriot's Day in the Commonwealth of Massachusetts and the day of the 116th running of the Boston Marathon.  It'll be a hot one with a predicted high of 84.  The 26.2 miles exact a terrible toll on the mortal coil.  Remember Pheidippides! who collapsed at the Athenian end of his run.  It may have been Frank Shorter who quipped, at the 20-mile mark, "Why couldn't Pheidippides have died now?"

Will Boston Billy be running today?

Helmuth James von Moltke

I  sometimes express skepticism about the value of the study of history. If history has lessons, they don't seem applicable to the present in any useful way. But there is no denying that history is a rich source of exemplary lives. These exemplary lives show what is humanly possible and furnish existential ideals. Helmuth James von Moltke was a key figure in the German resistance to Hitler. The Nazis executed him in 1945. Here is his story.  Here is an obituary of his wife, Freya.

Should We Abandon the Deep Problems for Problems Amenable to Solution?

UPDATE: London Ed does an excellent job of misunderstanding the following post.  Bad comments incline me to keep my ComBox closed.  But his is open.

Fred Sommers' "Intellectual Autobiography" begins as follows:

I did an undergraduate major in mathematics at Yeshiva College and went on to graduate studies in philosophy at Columbia University in the 1950s.  There I found that classical philosophical problems were studied as intellectual history and not as problems to be solved.  That was disappointing but did not strike me as unreasonable; it seemed to me that tackling something like "the problem of free will" or "the problem of knowledge" could take up one's whole life and yield little of permanent value.  I duly did a dissertation on Whitehead's process philosophy and was offered a teaching position at Columbia College.  Thereafter I was free to do philosophical research of my own choosing. My instinct was to avoid the seductive, deep problems and to focus on finite projects that looked amenable to solution. (The Old New Logic: Essays on the Philosophy of Fred Sommers, ed. Oderberg, MIT Press, 2005, p. 1)

 Sommers says something similar in the preface to his  The Logic of Natural Language (Oxford, 1982), p. xii:

My interest in Ryle's 'category mistakes' turned me away from the study of Whitehead's metaphysical writings (on which I had written a doctoral thesis at Columbia University) to the study of problems that could be arranged for possible solution.

What interests me in these two passages is the reason that Sommers gives for turning away from the big 'existential' questions of philosophy (God, freedom, immortality, and the like) to the problems of logical theory.  I cannot see that it is a good reason. (And he does seem to be giving a reason and not merely recording a turn in his career.)

The reason is that the problems of logic, but not those of metaphysics, can be "arranged for possible solution." Although I sympathize with Sommers' sentiment, he must surely have noticed that his attempt to rehabilitate pre-Fregean logical theory issues in results that are controversial, and indeed just as controversial as the claims of metaphysicians. Or do all his colleagues in logic agree with him?

The problems that Sommers tackles in his magisterial The Logic of Natural Language  are no more amenable to solution than the "deep, seductive" ones that could lead a philosopher astray for a lifetime.  The best evidence of  this is that Sommers has not convinced his MPL (modern predicate logic) colleagues. At the very most, Sommers has shown that TFL (traditional formal logic) is a defensible rival system.

If by 'pulling in our horns' and confining ourselves to problems of language and logic we were able to attain sure and incontrovertible results, then there might well be justification for setting metaphysics aside and working on problems amenable to solution. But if it turns out that logical, linguistic, phenomenological, epistemological and all other such preliminary inquiries arrive at results that are also widely and vigorously contested, then the advantage of 'pulling in our horns' is lost and we may as well concentrate on the questions that really matter, which are most assuredly not questions of logic and language — fascinating as these may be.

Given that the "deep, seductive" problems and those of logical theory are in the same boat as regards solubility, Sommer's' reason for devoting himself to logic over the big questions is not a good one.  The fact that philosophy of logic is often  more rigorous than 'big question' philosophy is not to the point.  The distinction between the rigorous and the unrigorous cuts perpendicular to that between the soluble and the insoluble.  And in any case, any philosophical problem can be tackled as rigorously as you please.

Sommers' is a rich and fascinating book. But, at the end of the day, how important is it to prove that the inference embedded in 'Some girl is loved by every boy so every boy loves a girl' really is capturable, pace the dogmatic partisans of modern predicate logic, by a refurbished traditional term logic? (See pp. 144-145) As one draws one's last breath, which is more salutary: to be worried about a silly b agatelle such as the one just mentioned, or to be contemplating God and the soul?

And shouldn't we philosophers who are still a ways from our last breaths devote our main energies to such questions as God and the soul over the trifles  of logic?

It would be nice if we could set philosophy on the "sure path of science" (Kant) by abandoning metaphysics and focusing on logic (or phenomenology or whatever one considers foundational).   But so far, this narrowing of focus and 'pulling in of one's horns' has availed nothing.  Philosophical investigation has simply become more technical, labyrinthine, and specialized.  All philosophical problems are in the same boat with respect to solubility.  A definitive answer to 'Are there atomic propositions?' (LNL, ch. 1) is no more in the offing than a definitive answer to 'Does God exist?' or 'Is the will libertarianly free?'

Ask yourself: what would be more worth knowing if it could be known?

Federalism and Governmental Competition

Conservatives understand that competition is good.  It breeds excellence.  And contrary to what some liberals think, competition that breeds excellence is not opposed to cooperation but presupposes it.  We need more competition, not less, and we need it at the level of government not just in the business world and in our private lives.

How is governmental competition possible?  Via federalism.  See Competition is Healthy for Governments, Too.

Obama and his ilk oppose federalism.  Obama must go.  And with him his ilk.

Vanity Plates

I reckon most motorists find vanity plates distasteful.   Upon seeing a plate bearing the letters 'Ph.D.' or 'M.D.' or 'J.D.,' the response is likely to be: BFD! In any case, who needs vanity plates when one can have for free one's very own vanity blog? And weblogs have this advantage: they are not in people's faces. You must freely decide to visit a site, and if you don't like what you find there, you bear at least half of the blame.

Movie Notes: The History Boys

From the old blog, originally posted 29 December 2006:

Most movies are trash, but not all, as witness The History Boys. It was well worth the drive to Scottsdale yesterday. Anyone serious about the humanities, from either side of the lectern, should enjoy it. It  has much of what I look for in a movie: plenty of wit and intelligence; good dialogue; subtlety and the sort of ambiguity of which real life is replete; little 'action': no race & chase, smash & crash (except for a small bit near the end that had a reason for being there); no special effects of the sort that the crapsters of HollyWeird serve up to satisfy the adolescent needs of the sensation-addicted and stupefied; no gratuitous sex and violence, though there is sex, mainly of the homosexual sort; and perhaps most important, no attempt to manipulate the thoughts and emotions of the viewer. Instead, an entertaining raising of questions and posing of problems.

My favorite line was a quotation from A. E. Housman: "All human knowledge is precious whether or not it serves the slightest human  use."

Near the end there is the reasonably pessimistic suggestion that the humanities are dead, at least at the universities. But Hector the humanist's call to "Pass it on!" also comes through. It brought a tear
to this curmudgeon's eye, and a thought to his head: if the universities become inhospitable to the transmission of high culture, then the job will have to be done in venues like this.

Are You an Introvert?

The bolded material below is taken verbatim from Susan Cain, Quiet: The Power of Introverts in a World that Can't Stop Talking (Crown 2012), p. 13.  I then give my responses.  The more affirmative responses, the more of an introvert you are.

1. I prefer one-on-one conversations to group activities. Absolutely!  Especially in philosophical discussions.  As Roderick Chisholm once said, "In philosophy, three's a crowd."

2. I often prefer to express myself in writing.  Yes. 

3. I enjoy solitude.  Is the Pope Catholic?  Beata solitudo, sola beatitudo.  Happy solitude, the sole beatitude.

4. I seem to care less than my peers about wealth, fame, and status.  Seem?  Do!  Money is a mere means.  To pursue it as an end in itself is perverse.  And once you have enough, you stop acquiring more and turn to higher pursuits.   Obscurity is delicious.  To be able to walk down the street and pass as an ordinary schmuck is wonderful.  The value of fame and celebrity is directly proportional to the value of the fools and know-nothings who confer it.  And doesn't Aristotle say that to  be famous you need other people, which fact renders you dependent on them? Similarly with social status.  Who confers it? And what is their judgment worth?

5. I dislike small talk, but I enjoy talking in depth about topics that matter to me.  More than once in these pages have I ranted about the endless yap, yap, yap, about noth, noth, nothing.

6. People tell me I'm a good listener.  Yes.  My mind drifts back to a girl I knew when I was fifteen.  She called me her 'analyst' when she wasn't calling me 'Dr. Freud.'

7. I'm not a big risk-taker.  That's right.  I recently took a three-day motorcycle course, passed it, and got my license.  I  had been eyeing  the Harley-Davidson 883 Iron.  But then I asked myself how riding a motorcycle would further my life tasks and whether it makes sense, having come this far, to risk my life and physical integrity in pursuit of cheap thrills.

8. I enjoy work that allows me to "dive in" with few interruptions.  Right.  No instant messaging.  Only recently acquired a cell phone.  I keep it turned off.  Call me the uncalled caller.  My wife is presently in a faraway land on a Fulbright.  That allows me to unplug the land-line.  I love e-mail; fast but unintrusive.  I'll answer when I feel like it and get around to it.  I don't allow mself to be rushed or interrupted.

9. I like to celebrate birthdays on a small scale, with only one or two close friends or family members.  I don't see the point of celebrating birthdays at all. What's to celebrate?  First, birth is not unequivocally good.  Second, it is not something you brought about.  It befell you.  Better to celebrate some good thing that you made happen.

10. People describe me as "soft-spoken" or "mellow."  I'm too intense to be called 'mellow,' but sotto voce applies.

11. I prefer not to show or discuss my work with others until it is finished.  Pretty much, with the exception of these blog scribblings. 

12. I dislike conflict.  Can't stand it.  Hate onesidedness.  I look at a problem from all angles and try to mediate oppositions  when possible.  I thoroughly hate, reject, and abjure the blood sport approach to philosophy.  Polemic has no place in philosophy.  This is not to say that it does not have a place elsewhere, in politics for example. 

13. I do my best work on my own.  Yes.  A former colleague, a superficial extrovert, once described me as 'lone wolf.'

14. I tend to think before I speak.  Yes.

15. I feel drained after being out and about, even if I've enjoyed myself.  Yes.  This is a common complaint of introverts.  They can take only so much social interaction.  It depletes their energy and they need to go off by themselves to 'recharge their batteries.'  In my case, it is not just an energy depletion but a draining away of my  'spiritual substance.'  It is as if one's interiority has been compromised and one has entered into inauthenticity, Heidegger's Uneigentlichkeit.  The best expression of this sense of spiritual depletion is probably Kierkegaard's remark in one of his early journal entries about a party he attended:

I have just returned from a party of which I was the life and soul; witty banter flowed from my lips, everyone laughed and admired me — but I came away, indeed that dash should be as along as the radii of the earth's orbit ———————————————————- wanting to shoot myself. (1836)

16. I often let calls go through to e-mail.  Yes. See comment to #8 above.

17. If I had to choose, I'd prefer a weekend with absolutely nothing to do to one with too many things scheduled.  I love huge blocks of time, days at a stretch, with no commitments whatsoever. Dolce far niente.  Sweet to do nothing.

18. I don't enjoy multitasking.  Right. One thing at a time.

19. I can concentrate easily.  Obviously, and for long stretches of time.

20. In classroom sitations, I prefer lecture to seminars.  Especially if I'm doing the lecturing.

Here is a description of the Myers-Briggs INTP.  And here is another.

David Brightly’s Weblog and a Punctilio Anent Predication and Inclusion

The unduly modest David Brightly has begun a weblog entitled tillyandlola, "scribblings of no consequence."   In a recent post he criticizes my analysis of the invalidity of the argument: Man is a species; Socrates is a man; ergo, Socrates is a species.  I claimed that the argument equivocates on 'is.'  In the major premise, 'is' expresses a relation of conceptual inclusion: the concept man includes the subconcept species.  In the minor premise, however, the 'is' is the 'is' of predication: Socrates falls under man, he doesn't fall within it.

I am afraid that my analysis is faulty, however, and for the reasons that David gives.  There is of course a difference between the 'is' of inclusion and the 'is' of predication.  'Man is an animal' expresses the inclusion of the concept animal within the concept man.  'Socrates is a man,' however, does something different: it expresses the  fact that Socrates falls under the concept man

But as David notes, it is not clear that species is included within the concept man.  If we climb the tree of Porphyry we will ascend from man to mammal to animal; but nowhere in our ascent will we hit upon species

‘Institutionalized Racism’

Liberals love the phrase, 'institutionalized racism.'  A  racist society it is in which so many blacks achieve high political office despite the fact that blacks are a small minority of the population.  Indeed, we have a black president.  What better proof that racism is inscribed into our institutional structure?  But then again, Obama is only half black.  If George Zimmerman of Trayvon Martin fame is a 'white Hispanic' as maintained in the Solomonic pages of the New York Times, then, by parity of reasoning, Barack Obama is a 'white black.'  Is that perhaps the proof of institutional racism?  You see, if the USA were not institutionally racist, then we would have a black-black president by now.

Of course I am being sarcastic.  In dealing with notions as preternaturally idiotic as those of liberals, mockery, derision, sarcasm and the like are more effective than patient argument.  Reason and argument are effective only with those who inhabit the plane of reason. There is no point in talking sense to the denizens of the planet Unsinn.   Or if you are not in the mood to mock and deride them, if you are feeling charitable, then offer your help and therapy.  Those who are beneath reason do not need refutation; they need therapy.  They need care.  And we conservatives do care.  We want you liberals to be happy and successful and less stupid.  Of course we are honest enough to admit that our motive is partially selfish: the less stupid and unsuccessful and unhappy you are, the better it will be for us.

Actually, what we need is a 'proctology' of the liberal.  We need to understand how so many heads can inhabit that region where the sun doesn't shine.  But understanding is not enough: we need practical methods of extraction.  My fear, however, is that even an army of proctologists, each member of which enjoys the life span of a Methuselah, would not be able to bring the shrunken pate of even one liberal into the light of day.

And that's a pity. (I have successfully resisted the temptation to engage in scatological alliteration.)

For an example of the sort of idiocy I am excoriating, see here; for an antidote, go here.

Arguments and Proofs in Philosophy

London Ed writes:

Philosophers always refer to their arguments as 'arguments' and never as 'proofs'. This is because there is nothing in the entire, nearly three thousand year history of philosophy that would count as a proof of anything. Nothing.

This obiter dictum illustrates how, by exaggerating and saying something that is strictly false, one can still manage to convey a truth.  The truth is that there is very little in the history of philosophy that could count as a proof of anything.  But of course some philosophers do refer to their arguments as proofs.  Think of those Thomists who speak of proofs of the existence of God.  And though no Thomist accepts the ontological 'proof,' there are philosophers who refer to the ontological argument as a proof.  The Germans also regularly speak of der ontologische Gottesbeweis rather than of das ontologische Argument.  For example, Frege in a famous passage from the Philosophy of Arithmetic writes,  Weil Existenz Eigenschaft des Begriffes ist, erreicht der ontologische Beweis von der Existenz Gottes sein Ziel nicht. (sec. 53)

These quibbles aside, an argument is not the same as a proof.  'Prove' is a verb of success.  The same goes for 'disprove' and 'refute.'  But 'argue' is not.  I may argue that p without establishing that p.  But if I prove that p, then I establish that p.  Indeed, I establish it as true. 

Why has almost nothing ever been proven in the history of philosophy? 

It is because for an argument to count as a proof in philosophy — I leave aside mathematics which may not be so exactingcertain exceedingly demanding conditions must be met.  First, a proof must be deductive: no inductive argument proves its conclusion.  Second, a proof must be valid: it must be a deductive argument such that its corresponding conditional is a narrowly-logical truth, where an argument's corresponding conditional is a conditional proposition the protasis of which is the conjunction of the argument's premises, and the apodosis of which is the argument's conclusion.

Third, although a valid argument needn't have true premises, a proof must have all true premises.  In other words, a proof must be a sound argument.  Fourth, a proof cannot commit any infomal fallacy such as petitio principii.  An argument from p to p is deductive, valid, and sound.  But it is obviously no proof of anything.

Fifth, a proof must have premises that are not only true, but known to be true by the producers and the consumers of the argument.  This is because a proof is not an argument considered in abstracto but a method for generating knoweldge for some cognizer.  For example, if I do not know that I am thinking,then I cannot use that premise in a proof that I exist. 

Sixth,  a proof in philosophy must have premises all of which are known to be true in a sense of 'know' that entails absolute impossibilty  of mistake.  Why set the bar so high?  Well, if you say that you have proven the nonexistence of God, say, or that the self is but a bundle of perceptions, or that freedom of the will is an illuison, or whatever, and one of your premises is such that I can easily conceive its being false, then you haven't proven anything. You haven't rationally compelled me to accept your conclusion. You may have given a 'good' argument in the sense of a 'reasonable' argument where that is one which satisfies my first four conditions; but you haven't given me a compelling argument, an argument which is such that, were I to reject it I would brand myself as irrational.  (Of course the only compulsion here at issue is rational compulsion, not ad baculum (ab baculum?) compulsion.)

Given my exposition of the notion of proof in philosophy, I think it is clear that very little has ever been proven in philosophy. I am pretty sure that London Ed, as cantankerous and contrary as he is known to be, will agree.  But he goes further: he says that nothing has ever been proven in philosophy.

But hasn't the sophomoric relativist been refuted?  He maintains that it is absolutely true that every truth is relative.  Clearly, the sophomoric relativist contradicts himself and refutes himself.  One might object to this example by claiming that no philosopher has ever been a sophomoric relativist.  But even if that is so, it is a possible philosophical position and one that is provably mistaken. Or so say I.

Or consider a sophist like Daniel Dennet who maintains (in effect) that consciousness is an illusion.  That is easily refuted and I have done the job more than once in these pages.  But it is such a stupid thesis that it is barely worth refuting.  Its negation — that consciousness is not an illusion — is hardly a substantive thesis.  A substantive thesis would be: Consciousness is not dependent for its existence on any material things or processes.

There is also the stupidity of that fellow Krauss who thinks that nothing is something.  Refuting this nonsense hardly earns one a place in the pantheon of philosophers.

Nevertheless, I am in basic agreement with London Ed:  Nothing of any real substance has ever been proven in philosophy.  No one has ever proven that God exists, that God does not exist, that existence is a second-level property, that there is a self, that there is no self, that the will is free, that the will is not free, and so on.

Or perhaps you think you have a proof of some substantive thesis?  Then I'd like to hear it.  But it must be a proof in my exacting sense. 

The Illiberalism of Contemporary Liberals

When I attack liberals it is always contemporary liberals that I have in my sights.  I myself am in several ways a classical liberal.  What I object to in contemporary liberals, or 'progressives' as they like to call themselves, is their extremism and their illiberalism.  Peter Berkowitz has an excellent article on progressive illiberalism.

There is more true liberalism in today's conservatives than in today's 'liberals.'