Remember John Belushi who took the 'speedball' (heroin + cocaine) express to Kingdom Come? Or perhaps you recall the ill-starred Chris Farley who took the same train. It is 'sobering' to work through the litany of celebrities who chose (whether proximately or ultimately) a drug- or alcohol-fueled exit from the mundus sensibilis.
Month: March 2010
The Good Life
People think they know what the good life is. Do they? I know one thing about the good life: the inquiry into what it is is essential to it.
The Cowardice of One’s Convictions
Some are praised for having the courage of their convictions. But if one has the wrong convictions, it would be better were one to have the cowardice of one's convictions.
Could a Concrete Individual be a Truthmaker?
Could a concrete individual such as the man Peter function as a truthmaker? Peter Lupu and I both find this idea highly counterintuitive. And yet many contemporary writers on truth and truthmaking have no problem with it. They have no problem with the notion that essential predications about x are made true by x itself, for any x. Assume that the primary truthbearers are Fregean propositions and consider the Fregean proposition *Peter is human.* (Asterisks around a declarative sentence form a name of the Fregean proposition expressed by the sentence.) Being human is an essential property of Peter: it is a property he has in every possible world in which he exists. It follows that there is no world in which Peter exists and *Peter is human* is not true. Hence Peter himself logically suffices for the truth of *Peter is human.* Similarly for every essential predication involving our man. Why then balk at the notion that a concrete individual can serve as a truthmaker?
Here is an argument in support of balking:
1. Every asymmetric relation is irreflexive. (Provable within first-order predicate logic. Exercise for the reader: prove it!)
2. Truthmaking is an asymmetric relation. If T makes true *p*, then *p* does not make true T.
3. Truthmaking is irreflexive. (From 1, 2)
4. Whatever makes true a proposition admitting of existential generalization also makes true the proposition which is its existential generalization. For example, if Peter makes true *Peter is human,* then Peter makes true the existential generalization *There are humans.* And if *Peter is human* makes true **Peter is human* is a proposition,* then *Peter is human* makes true *There are propositions.* (It is a universally accepted axiom of truthmaking that one and the same truthmaker can make true more than one truthbearer. Truthmaking is not a one-to-one relation.)
5. If a concrete individual, by itself and in virtue of its mere existence, can make a true an essential predication about it, then an entity of any ontological category can, by itself and in virtue of its mere existence, make true an essential predication about it. And conversely. For example, if Peter makes true *Peter is human,* then *Peter is human* makes true **Peter is human* is a proposition* and also **Peter is human* is an abstract object,* etc. And conversely: if *Peter is human* makes true **Peter is human* is a proposition,* then Peter makes true *Peter is human.*
6. *There are propositions* is essentially a proposition.
7. A concrete individual, by itself and in virtue of its mere existence, can make true an essential predication about it.
8. *There are propositions* is made true by *Peter is human* and indeed by any proposition, including *There are propositions.* (From 4, 5, 6, 7. To spell it out: Peter makes true *Peter is human* by 7; *Peter is human* makes true **Peter is human* is a proposition* by 5 and 6. *There are propositions* is the existential generalization of **Peter is human* is a proposition.* *Peter is human* makes true *There are propositions* by 4. *Peter is human,*, however, can be replaced by any proposition in this reasoning. Therefore, *There are propositions* is made true by any proposition including *There are propositions.*
9. *There are propositions* has itself as one of its truthmakers. (From 8)
10. It is not the case that truthmaking is irreflexive. (From 9. Note that when we say of a relation that it has a property such as symmetry or irreflexivity, we mean that that has this property essentially.)
11. (10) contradicts (3).
12. One of the premises is false. (From 11)
13. The only premises that are even remotely controvertible are (2) and (7).
14. (2), which affirms the asymmetry of truthmaking, cannot be reasonably denied. Why not? Well, the whole point of truthmaking is to provide a metohysical, not empirical, explanation of the truth of truthbearers. Explanation, however, is asymmetric by its very nature: if x explains y, then y does not explain x.
15. (7) is false: it it not the case that a concrete individual, by itself, can serve as a truthmaker.
Credit where credit is due: The above is my attempt to put into a rigorous form some remarks of Marian David which point up the tension between the asymmetry of truthmaking and the notion that concrete individuals, by themselves, can serve as the truthmakers for essential predications about them. See his essay "Truth-making and Correspondence" in Truth and Truth-Making, eds. Lowe and Rami. McGill 2009, 137-157, esp. 152-154.
Scholastic Realism and Predication
This post continues our explorations in the philosophy of The School. What is a scholastic realist? John Peterson (Introduction to Scholastic Realism, Peter Lang, 1999, p. 6) defines a scholastic realist as follows:
S is a scholastic realist =df i) S is a moderate realist and ii) S believes that universals exist in some transcendent mind, i.e., the mind of God.
A moderate realist is defined like this:
S is a moderate realist =df i) S denies that universals exist transcendently and ii) S affirms that universals exist immanently both in matter and minds.
A universal exists transcendently just in case it exists "independently of matter and mind." One who holds that universals exist independently of matter and mind is a Platonic or extreme realist. A moderate realist who is not a scholastic realist Peterson describes as an Aristotelian realist. Such a philosopher is a moderate realist who "denies that universals exist in some transcendent mind." In sum, and interpreting a bit:
Platonic or extreme realist: maintains that there are universals and that they can exist transcendently, i.e., unexemplified (uninstantiatied) and so apart from matter and mind.
Moderate realist: denies that there are any transcendent universals and maintains that universals exist only immanently in minds and in matter.
Scholastic realist: moderate realist who believes that there is a transcendent mind in which universals exist.
Aristotelian realist: moderate realist who denies that there is a transcendent mind in which universals exist.
On Reading Philosophers For the Beauty of Their Prose
To read a philosopher for the beauty of his prose alone is like ordering a delicacy in a world-class restaurant for its wonderful aroma and artful presentation — but then not eating it.
I had that thought one morning while re-reading for the fifth time William James' magisterial essay, The Moral Philosopher and the Moral Life. So rich in thought, and yet so distracting in its beauty the prose in which the thoughts are couched. James and a few other philosophers are great writers — Schopenhauer and Santayana come to mind — but the thought's the thing.
Leftist Terms of Abuse
Here is a partial list of terms liberals/ leftists apply to virtually every idea or action or person with which or with whom they differ:
Racist
Sexist
Xenophobic
Homophobic
Islamophobic
Imperialist
Bigoted
Intolerant
Risks of Desert Hiking
In a society made litigious by an excess of lawyers, the need for various CYA maneuvers is correspondingly great. One such is the disclaimer. I particularly enjoy the disclaimers found in well-written hiking books. Rare is the hiking book that doesn't have one these days. The following is from local author,Ted Tenny, Goldfield Mountain Hikes, p. 4:
The risks of desert hiking include, but are not limited to: heatstroke, heat exhaustion, heat prostration, heat cramps, sunburn, dehydration, flash floods, drowning, freezing, hypothermia, getting lost, getting stranded after dark, falling, tripping, being stung, clawed or bitten by venomous or non-venomous creatures, being scratched or stuck by thorny plants, being struck by lightning, falling rocks, natural or artificial objects falling from the sky, or a comet colliding with the Earth.
Still up for a hike?
Feser on Stupak
Stupak's Enablers. This is a very rich post bristling with important distinctions. Excerpt:
There can be no question, then, that while the Church allows that government can legitimately intervene in economic life and in other ways come to the assistance of those in need, she also teaches that there is a presumption in justice against such intervention, a presumption which can be overridden only when such intervention is strictly necessary, only to the extent necessary, and only on the part of those governmental institutions which are as close as possible to those receiving the aid in question. This surely follows from the principles of subsidiarity and the priority of the family. And it surely rules out not only libertarianism but also the sorts of policy preferences typical of socialists, social democrats, and egalitarian liberals.
I wonder how many Catholic bishops could explain the principle of subsidiarity? Too many of them are too busy being leftists to comprehend and transmit Catholic social teaching.
Nerd, Geek, Dweeb, and Dork
Ever fret over the correct use of these terms? This Venn diagram will set you straight. (HT: Mike Valle. From this site.)
Why not be a Nominalist?
0. This post is a sequel to Truthmaker Maximalism Questioned.
1. On one acceptation of the term, a nominalist is one who holds that everything that exists is a concrete individual. Nominalists accordingly eschew such categories of entity as: universals, whether transcendent or immanent, Fregean propositions, Castaneda's ontological operators, mathematical sets, tropes (abstract particulars, perfect particulars), and concrete states of affairs. Nominalists of course accept that there are declarative sentences and that some of them are true. Consider the true
1. Peter is hungry.
Nominalists cheerfully admit that the proper name 'Peter' denotes something external to language and mind, a particular man, which we can call the 'ontological correlate' of the subject term. But, ever wary of "multiplying entities beyond necessity," nominalists fight shy of admitting an ontological correlate of 'hungry,' let alone a correlate of 'is.' And yet, given that (1) is true, 'hungry' is true of Peter. (In a simple case like this, the predicate is true of the the referent of the subject term iff the sentence is true.) Now philosophers like me are wont to ask: In virtue of what is 'hungry' true of Peter? Since 'hungry' applies to Peter in the way in which 'leprous,' 'anorexic,' and other predicates do not, I find it reasonable to put the same question as follows: What is the ontological ground of the correct application of 'hungry' to Peter?
2. In answering this question I introduce two posits that will enrage the nominalist and offend against his ontologcal parsimoniousness. First of all, we need an o-correlate of 'hungry.' I admit of course that 'hungry' in our sample sentence functions differently than 'Peter.' The latter is a name, the former is what Frege calls a concept-word (Begriffswort). Nevertheless, there must be something in reality that corresponds to 'hungry,' and whatever it is it cannot be identical to Peter. Why not? Well, Peter, unlike my cat, is not hungry at every time at which he exists; and for every time t in the actual world at which he is hungry, there is some possible world in which he is not hungry at t. Therefore, Peter cannot be identical to the o-correlate of 'hungry.'
We are back to our old friend (absolute numerical) identity which is an equivalence relation (reflexive, symmetrical, transitive) governed by the Indiscernibility of Identicals and the Necessity of Identity.
3. But why do we need an o-correlate of 'hungry' at all? I asked: in virtue of what is 'hungry' true of Peter? One sort of nominalist, the 'ostrich nominalist,' will say that there is nothing in virtue of which 'hungry' is true of Peter. For him is is just a 'brute fact,' i.e., an inexplicable datum, that 'hungry' correctly applies to Peter. There is no need of an ontological ground of the correctness of this application. There is no room for a special philosophical explanation of why 'hungry' is true of Peter. It just applies to him, and that's the end of the matter. The ostrich nominalist of course grants that Peter's being hungry can be explained 'horizontally' in terms of antecedent and circumambient empirical causes; what he denies is that there is need for some further 'philosophical' or 'metaphysical' or 'ontological' explanation of the truth of 'Peter is hungry.'
If a nominalist says that 'hungry' is true of Peter because Peter is hungry, then I say he moves in a circle of embarrasingly short diameter. What we want to understand are the ontological commitments involved in the true sentence, 'Peter is hungry.' We need more than Peter. We need something that grounds the correctness of the application of 'hungry' to him. To say that 'hungry' is true of Peter because Peter is hungry presupposes what we are trying to understand. Apart from this diversionary tactic, the ostrich nominalist is back to saying that there is nothing extralingusitic that grounds the correct application of 'hungry' to Peter. He is denying the possibility of any metaphysical explanation here. He is saying that it is just a brute fact that 'hungry' applies to Peter.
4. As for my second posit, I would urge that introducing an o-correlate for 'hungry' such as a universal tiredness does not suffice to account for the truth of the sample sentence. And this for the simple reason that Peter and tiredness could both exist withough Peter being tired. What we need is a concrete state of affairs, an entity which, though it has Peter and tiredness as constituents, is distinct from each and from the mereological sum of the two.
5. Now one can argue plausibly against both posits. And it must be admitted that both posits give rise to conundra that cast doubt on them. But what is the alternative? Faced with a problem, the ostrich sticks his head in the sand. Out of sight, out of mind. Similarly. the ostrich nominalist simply ignores the problem. Or am I being unfair?
Perhaps the issue comes down to this: Must we accept the truth of sentences like (1) as a 'brute fact,' i.e. as something insusceptible of explanation (apart, of course, from causal explanation), OR is there the possibility of a philosophical account?
6. Finally, it is worth nothing that the nominalist blunders badly if he says that Peter is hungry in virtue of 'hungry''s applying to him. For that is a metaphysical theory and an absurd one to boot: it makes Peter's being hungry depend on the existence of the English predicate 'hungry.' To avoid an incoherent, Goodmanaical, linguistic idealism, the nominalist should give no metaphysical explanation and be content to say it is just a brute fact that Peter is hungry.
Saturday Night at the Oldies: Two Watusi Numbers
Ray Barretto, El Watusi, 1963. I remember when it first came out, but you young whippersnappers may remember it from Carlito's Way. Don't ask me what it means. The Orlons, Wah-Watusi, 1962.
The Health Care Debate: What It’s Really About
Here. Fidel congratulates Obama. Excerpt from the second article:
Doctors haven’t benefited very much, either, from Cuba’s health care “miracle.” Because they earn the equivalent of only about $20 U.S. per month, Cuban physicians have quit the medical profession in droves — turning instead to the only industry that offers them any degree of economic opportunity: the Cuban tourism industry. It is not uncommon to see former doctors driving cabs, working as tour guides, or waiting tables in restaurants and family inns in Havana.
People need to bear in mind that there is more to health care than health care insurance. The best coverage in the world is worthless without health care providers: doctors, nurses, lab technicians, and all the rest. Socialist schemes, based as they are on ignorance of human nature, remove incentives. Why would any one put up with the rigors of medical school, internship, long hours, malpractice harrassment and the like to work for the government?
Brew 102
I asked an old friend if he remembered the huge Brew 102 sign visible from a Los Angeles freeway back in the '50s and '60s. (See photo below.) His response:
'Deed I do remember Brew 102.
Over the Hollywood Freeway.
My arm 'round a cutie in a '55 Buick
Goin' long 'ol Highway 101.
Here is my verse response which is not meant autobiographically:
'Twas Brew 102 that did me in
And got me to drownin' in liquid sin
Soon I was a rollin' down that lost highway
Where many a boy has been known to stray
On 66 I got my kicks
And on 101 I had my fun.
But now I'm here to tell you true
We ain't on this earth to booze and screw
The female ass and the whisky glass
Have brought many a man to a sorry pass.
That's my wisdom take it straight
And head while there's time for the narrow gate
It's not too late and it's not too far
As long's you don't stop at the next whisky bar.
LaLaLand in the 1950s, Hollywood Freeway, and Brew 102 sign (left-click to enlarge):
Truthmaker Maximalism Questioned
For Peter Lupu discussions with whom helped me clarify my thoughts on this topic.
0. What David Armstrong calls Truthmaker Maximalism is the thesis that every truth has a truthmaker. Although I find the basic truthmaker intuition well-nigh irresistible, I have difficulty with the notion that every truth has a truthmaker. Thus I question Truthmaker Maximalism.
1. Compare *Peter is tired* and *Every concretum is self-identical.* I will argue that propositions like the first have truthmakers while propositions like the second do not. (A declarative sentence enclosed in asterisks names the Fregean proposition expressed by the sentence. I will assume that the primary truthbearers are Fregean propositions. By definition, a truth is a true truthbearer.)
2. Intuitively, the first truth is in need of something external to it that 'makes' it true or determines it to be true, or serves as the ontological ground of its truth. By 'external to it,' I don't just mean that the truthmaker of a truth must be distinct from it: this condition is satisfied by a distinct proposition that entails it. What I mean is that the truthmaker must be both distinct from the truthbearer and not, like the truthbearer, a 'representational entity' where the latter term covers such items as sentences, contents of judgments, and Fregean propositions (the senses of context-free sentences in the indicative mood.) In other words, a truthmaker of a first-order truth such as *Peter is tired* must be outside the sphere of representations: it must be extralinguistic, extramental, and extra-propositional. Truthmakers, then, are 'in the world' in one sense of 'world.' They are ontological grounds of truth. Thus the truthmakers of propositions like *Peter is tired* cannot belong to the category of propositions. The ontological ground of such a proposition cannot be an entity within the sphere of propositions.